By Kevin D. Williamson
Thursday, December 28, 2017
It started with ferries.
Lord Chief Justice Hale considered the question of ferry
regulation in De Portibus Maris in
1670. Even if a man owns the land and docks on both sides of a river, and owns
a ferry that can be used to take people and cargo between them, he does not
have the right to operate a public conveyance without the king’s permission.
The king, Lord Hale insisted, has
a right of franchise or privilege,
that no man may set up a common ferry for all passengers, without a
prescription time out of mind, or a charter from the king. He may make a ferry
for his own use or the use of his family, but not for the common use of all the
king’s subjects passing that way; because it doth in consequence tend to a
common charge, and is become a thing of public interest and use, and every man
for his passage pays a toll, which is a common charge, and every ferry ought to
be under a public regulation, viz., that it give attendance at due times, keep
a boat in due order, and take but reasonable toll; for if he fail in these he
is finable. So if one owns the soil and landing-places on both banks of a
stream, he cannot use them for the purposes of a public ferry, except upon such
terms and conditions as the body politic may from time to time impose; and this
because the common good requires that all public ways shall be under the
control of the public authorities. This privilege or prerogative of the king,
who in this connection only represents and gives another name to the body
politic, is not primarily for his profit, but for the protection of the people
and the promotion of the general welfare.
The legal abstraction here is not too far removed from
the physical facts of the case: The would-be ferryman may own his boat, and he
may own docks on both sides of the river, but he does not own the river itself,
which is part of the commons and therefore to be regulated in the common
interest, which is what is meant by “general welfare.” Where private property
intersects with the public sphere, Lord Hale concluded, “it ceases to be juris privati only,” because it is
“affected with a public interest.”
This line of thinking has long been upheld as the
common-law basis for regulation of private property and private enterprise in
general. Lord Hale’s argument about ferries was over time expanded upon and
applied to enterprises that did not rely directly on the king’s waterways or
other public property but were instead merely involved in commerce that touched
these indirectly: wharves and warehouses, for example, and, in the United
States, grain silos, the regulation of which was challenged, unsuccessfully, in
the Supreme Court case Munn v. Illinois,
in which the Court’s opinion cited and relied heavily upon Lord Hale and his
royal ferry licensure. Somewhere along the way, the principle that business
transacted on and by means of public property may be regulated for the public
good was abstracted beyond recognition, and instead of asking who may use the
rivers for commercial purposes and on what terms, the law instead assumed that
the movement and storage of goods could be regulated at any point on the theory
that they probably crossed a river or were carried down the king’s highway at
some time. There was no limitation to this: However many degrees of separation
there might have been between a certain subsequent transaction and the king’s
interest in maintaining the waterways for public use, the king’s interest was
never diminished. Lord Hale didn’t have it quite right: Goods weren’t
“affected” with a public interest — they were infected by it, and the infection
was and is incurable. Hence the existence of natural commons such as rivers and
other navigable waterways, along with such contributions to the general welfare
as public roads and waterfront improvements, became a general license for
regulation. This is the origin of Senator Warren’s “You didn’t build that!” school of rhetoric.
It is the lack of a limiting principle that has always
alarmed critics of Lord Hale’s argument. If a barrel of wine takes on the
public interest when it crosses a river and then carries that interest with it,
effectively undiminished, everywhere it goes, then the public sphere is
effectively infinite, as is the mandate for regulation. In the American
context, the king’s command over the commons has been superseded most
significantly by the doctrine of “interstate commerce.” Like Hale’s ferry
principle, the idea of interstate commerce has proved elastic. One would think
that interstate commerce would consist only of those activities that are 1)
interstate and 2) commercial, but U.S. law has long made room for regulating
activities that might plausibly have some remote effect on interstate commerce.
In the infamous case of Wickard v.
Filburn, the Court held that Roscoe Filburn, a farmer, was subject to
federal regulation of his wheat output, which was limited under New Deal law,
even though he was growing wheat for his own use on his own farm rather than
trading it across state lines. The central planners of the Roosevelt
administration argued that they were pursuing a national interest in managing
wheat prices and that Filburn’s farm might have some conceivable effect on
them: If he grows his own wheat, he isn’t buying it on the interstate market.
The Court agreed, and we still live under that precedent.
From the regulation of public waterways comes the
principle that a man may not grow wheat on his own farm for his own use without
the king’s permission: The slope is, in fact, slippery.
The principle that private property takes on an
unalterably public character whenever a chicken crosses the road is central to
American civil-rights law — which, contrary to the account sometimes given by
our Democrat friends, has a history that does not begin in 1964.
In the course of a dispute over the Civil Rights Act of
1875, Lord Hale and his ferries were back on the minds of the justices of the
Supreme Court. Justice John Marshall Harlan argued that the longstanding legal
principles supporting the regulation of everything from grain silos to
railroads meant that “in every material sense applicable to the Fourteenth
Amendment, railroad corporations, keepers of inns, and managers of places of
public amusement are agents of the state.” Justice Joseph P. Bradley took a
different view, that the constitutional rights in question were limitations on
what the state may do, not limitations on what individuals and businesses may
do:
Individual invasion of individual
rights is not the subject-matter of the [Fourteenth] Amendment. It has a deeper
and broader scope. It nullifies and makes void all state legislation, and state
action of every kind, which impairs the privileges and immunities of citizens
of the United States, or which injures them in life, liberty, or property
without due process of law, or which denies to any of them the equal protection
of the laws.
. . . It does not invest Congress with power
to legislate upon subjects which are within the domain of state legislation;
but to provide modes of relief against state legislation, or state action, of
the kind referred to. It does not authorize Congress to create a code of
municipal law for the regulation of private rights; but to provide modes of
redress against the operation of state laws, and the action of state officers,
executive or judicial, when these are subversive of the fundamental rights
specified in the amendment. Positive rights and privileges are undoubtedly
secured by the Fourteenth Amendment; but they are secured by way of prohibition
against state laws and state proceedings affecting those rights and privileges.
Beyond the specific constitutional questions, Justice
Bradley was in search of a limiting principle: If the Fourteenth Amendment
means that obscure innkeepers and café operators are subject to the same
constitutional burdens as, say, the government of Alabama, then “it is
difficult to see where it is to stop.” Justice Bradley prevailed, and Justice
Harlan was the lone dissenter. In the debate over the Civil Rights Act of 1964,
the arguments were in many ways the same. Senator Goldwater, whose
long and distinguished record as a champion of civil rights has been strangely
forgotten, believed that the “public accommodations” language in the
proposed civil-rights legislation — provisions that would put into effect
Justice Harlan’s conception of private businesses as effective “agents of the
state” —was undesirable and unconstitutional, a perversion of Congress’s power
to regulate interstate commerce.
The rhetoric of the time was often heated and at times
indefensible. But no one, not the most wild-eyed critic of the principles
underlying the civil-rights legislation of the 1960s, ever suggested that, if
such laws were passed, they would lead to obscure Christian bakers’ being
forced at the point of government bayonets to produce cakes for the celebration
of homosexual weddings. (I write “principles” because the Masterpiece case is a challenge to a Colorado statute, not to the
Civil Rights Act of 1964.) The slope is, in fact, slippery.
We ought to think a little about how far down the slope
we want to go. Americans look instinctively to our Constitution and to our
national political principles for guidance, and our attitude toward them is the
civic version of sola scriptura. We
tend to generalize when we ought to specify and sometimes to specify when we
ought to generalize. The social and political condition of African Americans in
the 1960s was indefensible and incompatible with our national ideals. Something
needed to be done, and something was, imperfectly. But our generalizing from
that has not always been intelligent or prudent or constructive. Jews often
were treated shabbily in our country, and sometimes still are, but the case
against Princeton’s numerus clausus system of discriminating against Jewish
applicants was not the same as the case against Mississippi’s suppression of
African Americans. The situation of gay Americans in 2017 is not very much like
that of black Americans in 1935.
It is not the case that discrimination is discrimination
is discrimination. Telling a black man that he may not work in your bank
because he is black is in reality a very different thing from telling a gay
couple that you’d be happy to sell them cupcakes or cookies or pecan pies but
you do not bake cakes for same-sex weddings — however much the principle of the
thing may seem superficially similar. If the public sphere is infinite, then
the private sphere does not exist, and neither does private life. Having a
bakery with doors open to the public does not make your business, contra
Justice Harlan, an agent of the state. A bakery is not the Commerce Department
or the local public high school.
Sure, bakery customers may travel there on public roads.
But tell me: Isn’t that EPA-regulated air you’re breathing?
No comments:
Post a Comment