By Charles C. W. Cooke
Tuesday, September 15, 2015
The United States, Senator Bernie Sanders declared before
a few thousand college students yesterday, was founded “from way back on racist
principles.” “That,” he added, after briefly apologizing for bringing the topic
up in the first instance, “is a fact — we have come a long way as a nation.”
The latter of these two asseverations is not in doubt.
Time was when a black American would be beaten, broken, and even skinned alive
on the flimsiest of pretexts, while his tormenters were let free without
charge. Conservatives occasionally like to wonder aloud what might happen if
this nation — or some part of it — were to be taken over by a monstrous and
unflinching tyranny. They do not need to treat the question as a hypothetical:
To read Ida B. Wells or Victoria Earle Matthews is to know the answer all too
well. That Sanders should remind voters of this truth is admirable and
necessary. That he should do so in the middle of an ideologically hostile crowd
is even more so. One cannot enjoy redemption without guilt, and, on occasion at
least, that guilt must be given a name. America has indeed “come a long way.”
It is unfortunate, however, that Sanders felt the need to
attach his reminder to a dangerous falsehood. The American escutcheon is indeed
sullied by original sin, but that sin is largely one of omission rather than commission.
Flawed as it is, the United States was not founded on inadequate or abominable
or “racist” principles, but upon extraordinary, revolutionary, and unusually
virtuous propositions that, tragically, have all too often been ignored. As
written, there is not a great deal wrong with the central tenets of the
Declaration of Independence; rather, the disgraces that pepper the history
books derive from the selective manner in which those tenets have been applied.
If one is so minded, one can reasonably propose that Revolution-era America was
chock-full of hypocrites, and that the lofty ideals to which the Founders paid
eloquent lip service were routinely disregarded when deemed inconvenient. But
to conclude that those ideals themselves are rotten is to commit an elemental
reasoning error. As one would not examine an incident of marital infidelity and
presume that the wedding vows must necessarily have been defective, one should
not infer from the Founders’ betrayals that their essential precepts were in some
way unsound. They weren’t. Man, as ever, is imperfect.
Likewise, one should refrain from blaming the founding
generation for the perfidy of its heirs. In Philadelphia, the Constitution’s
architects found themselves presented with two realistic choices. The first was
to contrive a new Constitution and, alas, to tolerate the continuation of
slavery. The second was to keep the existing Articles of Confederation, and,
alas, to tolerate the continuation of slavery. Wisely, they chose the former
path, conceding that abolition was impossible for now but electing to include
within the charter a number of salutary measures intended to encourage its
rescission. The Convention, James Madison confirmed during the debates,
“thought it wrong to admit in the Constitution the idea that there could be
property in men.” In the end, though, he was left with little choice. The
references are deliberately oblique: The existence of the institution is in
places acknowledged; there are obvious attempts to mitigate its corrupting
influence; and there is even a timetable for restriction. But there is no
abolition, and a careful reader will notice the joints. It is of its era.
Does this make the document an inherently corrupted work,
as Sanders implied? I think not, no. Indeed, if there is a related principle
within its structure, it is that slavery — which had existed almost everywhere
since time immemorial — would henceforth be limited. Frederick Douglass, a
former slave whose relationship with the young American republic was as
complicated as one might expect, eventually came to agree with this assessment.
Distancing himself from the cynicism of William Lloyd Garrison and the American
Anti-Slavery Society, Douglass concluded that the charter was unsullied. “In
that instrument I hold, there is neither warrant, license, nor sanction of the
hateful thing,” he supposed in July of 1852. “But, interpreted as it ought to
be interpreted, the Constitution is a GLORIOUS LIBERTY DOCUMENT. Read its
preamble, consider its purposes. Is slavery among them? Is it at the gateway?
Or is it in the temple? It is neither.” “Take the Constitution according to its
plain reading,” he concluded. “And I defy the presentation of a single
pro-slavery clause in it. On the other hand, it will be found to contain
principles and purposes, entirely hostile to the existence of slavery.”
That Douglass came to conclude that the Constitution
contains no “sanction” of human bondage — and, indeed that by “plain reading,”
it is “hostile” toward the practice — should not in truth be surprising.
Because the revolution had been fought at the call of both libertarian and
equalitarian rhetoric; because the Declaration of Independence contained a set
of universal propositions; and because so many blacks had participated
willingly in the fight for separation, a reconsideration of the status quo had
been inevitable from the moment the British surrendered at Yorktown. “Within
thirty years of Lexington and Concord, every northern state had acted to end
slavery, either immediately or gradually,” the historian John Ferling records
in Whirlwind. “Change was less spectacular in slavery’s heartland, the southern
states. Nevertheless, throughout the Upper South, state laws were revised making
it easier for slave owners to manumit their slaves, with the result that the
free black population witnessed a dramatic growth.” By 1810, the future looked
bright. In 1787, slavery had been outlawed in the Northwest territory. In 1808
— on the earliest date that the Constitution permitted Congress to act — the
slave trade had been brought to a swift end. And, outside of a few recalcitrant
pockets in the Deep South, it was broadly predicted that if the practice was
firmly restricted to a small part of the country, it would soon die out
completely.
This, as we now know, did not happen. And why not? Well,
because an ugly counter-ideal reared its head, and, tragically, took hold.
Writing to Henry L. Pierce in 1859, Abraham Lincoln lamented that, in many
parts of the slaveholding South, the Founders’ aspirations were gradually
giving way to a novel and deeply rotten philosophy. “It is now no child’s
play,” he calculated bitterly, “to save the principles of Jefferson from total
overthrow in this nation.” Once upon a time, the “definitions” and “axioms” of
the Declaration had been widely acknowledged. Now, where slavery remained in
force, they were openly rejected. “One dashingly calls them ‘glittering
generalities,’” Lincoln griped. “Another bluntly calls them ‘self evident
lies’; and still others insidiously argue that they apply only to ‘superior
races.’” Such claims, Lincoln contended, represented nothing more or less than
a blunt repudiation of the codified American creed.
He was correct. In a matter of decades, the reluctant and
primarily practical objections to manumission had been replaced by bold,
abstract justifications in its favor. Thomas Jefferson, Lincoln argued, had
exhibited “the coolness, forecast, and capacity to introduce into a merely
revolutionary document, an abstract truth, applicable to all men and all times,
and so to embalm it there, that to-day, and in all coming days, it shall be a
rebuke and a stumbling-block to the very harbingers of re-appearing tyranny and
oppression.” That stumbling block was now under fire.
How prescient Lincoln’s warning must have seemed two
years later when, on the eve of the Civil War, the vice president of the newly
minted Confederacy made the repudiation official. The Declaration of
Independence, Alexander Stephens proposed, had been built upon a falsehood.
Thomas Jefferson, now dead and buried, had been wrong. “The prevailing ideas
entertained by him and most of the leading statesmen at the time of the
formation of the old constitution,” Stephens argued, “were that the enslavement
of the African was in violation of the laws of nature; that it was wrong in
principle, socially, morally, and politically.” The core problem with the
Constitution, Stephens submitted, was not that it was the compromised product
of realpolitik, but that, like the Declaration before it, it actively presumed
that slavery would — and should — disappear. “They knew not well how to deal
with it,” Stephens noted with disdain. “But the general opinion of the men of
that day was that, somehow or other in the order of Providence, the institution
would be evanescent and pass away.” Such an idea, he concluded, was
“fundamentally wrong” and ought to be put aside by all civilized men. Whereas
the United States “rested upon the assumption of the equality of races,” the
Confederacy would be “founded upon exactly the opposite idea; its foundations
are laid, its corner- stone rests, upon the great truth that the negro is not
equal to the white man; that slavery subordination to the superior race is his
natural and normal condition.” The departure from the settlement of 1789 would
be dramatic. “This, our new government,” he submitted, “is the first, in the
history of the world, based upon this great physical, philosophical, and moral
truth.”
Mercifully, Stephens’s pernicious pseudo-“truth” was
smashed and cut into pieces by the Union Army, and the older, more virtuous
axioms were restored to the center of American life. Over the next century, by
a tricky combination of legal reform and social pressure, the unrealized values
of the founding were extended, little by little, to all. Today, we still
grapple with them — not because we suspect that they may be wrong but because
we worry that they are not being universally enjoyed and that this is
unacceptable. When the likes of Bernie Sanders submit that that the creed is
flawed per se, they do a disservice not only to America’s North Star — her
“promissory note” as Martin Luther King Jr. memorably put it — but to
themselves, for to advance the idea that warped men can by their behavior sully
self-evident truths is to side unwittingly with the Calhouns and the Stephenses
of the world, and to take firm aim at the hard-earned scars on Frederick
Douglass’s back.
No comments:
Post a Comment