By Ian Tuttle
Thursday, March 12, 2015
As usual, my colleague Charlie makes a sharp,
right-minded argument against today’s “attempt[s] to indict the entire
post-Ferguson activist movement” for the shooting of two Ferguson police
officers yesterday evening. Charlie’s points are well-taken, but I find his
criticisms a touch too sweeping.
That “society is to blame” is not the contention here (at
least, it is not mine; I will not speak for the oft-hyperbolic Twitter horde).
Rather, what has transpired since Michael Brown’s death in August is a
concerted effort by specific people in specific places at specific times to
perpetuate a narrative that is, and was, demonstrably largely untrue, and which
has informed, or accompanied, efforts among some of those same people to
deliberately gin up racial anger, and/or fear, to foment the particular form of
change they would like to see.
The specificity and demonstrability of this “culture” of
agitation is important. Charlie suggests that the Right’s condemnation in this
instance is akin to the Left’s condemnation of Sarah Palin for the 2011
shooting of Gabrielle Giffords. But of course the latter was bunk; there was
not a shred of evidence to suggest that Sarah Palin ever crossed Jared
Loughner’s mind. The Left’s Butterfly Effect–approach to political violence —
Sarah Palin flaps her gums here, and domestic terrorism rains down halfway
across the country — is not the case here, where specific anti-cop rhetoric has
been perpetrated by persons of influence in local communities, in the media,
and in government — and there is no question that it has been taken up by many
of the protesters recently on streets from Los Angeles to New York City.
Asserting the importance of not blaming the actions of lunatics on the martial
language of politicians need not preclude our ability to differentiate between
actual and made-up atmospheres of excitement.
If I understand him correctly, Charlie — even if he would
concede the above — erects a wall here between rhetoric and action. “Violent”
language is not violence. That is true, but it elides the mysterious way in
which words work on us. “We shall fight on the beaches…” bucked up wilting
spirits. It is not that rhetoric “justifies” any shooting; it is that it
creates an atmosphere that makes such events more likely.
And that means that there is, as Richard Weaver said, an
“ethics of rhetoric” of which we must be vigilant. That puts me at least
slightly odds with Charlie (always a dangerous place to be) on two last issues:
freedom of speech, and the moral autonomy of last night’s shooter.
We can defend freedom of speech while also recognizing
that certain speech does not contribute to the health of the body politic. Even
were the narrative of these protesters completely accurate, that would not
automatically excuse certain expressions.
That is, as is this last point, a distinction between
rule of law (the importance of which Charlie rightly insists) and moral
responsibility. We can — and should — maintain that the shooter is fully
legally responsible for his actions. But to insist that he was a completely
autonomous moral actor suggests that he was acting in some sort of moral vacuum
— which no one does. In this sense, then, we may be obliged to expand our sense
of “guilt” beyond the individual who pulled the trigger.
This is, though, a subtle distinction, and one that
requires a great deal of qualification and generosity when discussing. Since
neither of those is regularly welcome on cable news or Twitter, drawing this
distinction may be more dangerous than its benefits justify.
Still, we do well to remember that there are moral
questions that a polity must address that can never be adjudicated by the law,
and who is really to blame in Ferguson may be one such question.
No comments:
Post a Comment