By Robert VerBruggen
Friday, August 06, 2021
In Heller and McDonald, two
cases decided more than a decade ago, the Supreme Court held that the Second
Amendment protects an individual right to own a gun. Neither case presented the
issue of carrying a gun — but in the course of interpreting
the amendment for his Heller opinion, the late Antonin Scalia
laid out his thoughts. As the phrase is used in the Second Amendment, he wrote,
to “bear arms” is to carry weapons in case of confrontation.
A new case, New York State Pistol & Rifle Association v. Bruen,
seeks to cash that check. It’s a challenge to New York’s requirement that
applicants for concealed-carry licenses show “good cause,” or a non-speculative
need to carry a gun for self-defense, with local officials in charge of making
the determination. Especially in the state’s most left-leaning areas, it’s
incredibly difficult for the average person to get a permit.
But some academics are claiming, based on a new type of
research called “corpus analysis,” to have found fresh evidence that Scalia was
wrong. “Bearing arms,” they say, overwhelmingly referred to military service in
the Founding era, rather than simply referring to the carrying of weapons.
These scholars further suggest that Heller might have been
wrong more deeply — even when it comes to keeping arms —
though that is not the focus of the current case (and their “bear arms”
argument is generally recognized as their strongest).
In corpus analysis, researchers start with a massive
collection of writings or speech from a given time period (a “corpus”) and
search it for uses of a contested term. They can look at how the term was used
in context and count up how many times it was used in various ways. The
potential appeal to constitutional originalists, who want laws to be
interpreted by their “original public meaning” — the way an ordinary person
would have read them at the time they were enacted — is obvious. This is, after
all, a look at how people actually used words across a wide range of contexts.
So should the originalists on the Court reverse course,
holding that there’s no right to carry a gun outside of the militia, and open
the door to a broader reconsideration of Heller? Not unless they
were already on the fence.
This type of analysis can be useful, perhaps even
convincing in some circumstances. But despite its superficial appeal, it suffers from severe limitations that render it no more
compelling than any other approach to constitutional interpretation. It must be
treated skeptically, interpreted with care, and viewed as one small piece of
the puzzle alongside other forms of evidence — the evidence that the Court
already considered in the previous cases.
General Issues with Corpus Analysis
When a court interprets a tricky term, the question is
often whether the term’s “ordinary” meaning is broad enough to cover some
disputed conduct. But corpus analysis doesn’t tell us that. What it tells us,
instead, is how frequently people actually use the term to refer to the conduct
in question, relative to how often they use the term in other ways. This number
is not necessarily all that informative.
As Josh Blackman and James C. Phillips once noted, for example, if you checked a corpus for uses
of the verb “to read,” you’d probably find far more examples of people reading
newspapers than of people reading street signs — but the low frequency of
street-sign references would tell you nothing of importance. It would merely
reveal that people read newspapers more than they read street signs, or at
least more frequently discuss reading newspapers. A law
forbidding people “to read,” or a constitutional provision giving them a right
to, would presumably apply to street signs (and nutritional labels and ancient
scrolls) just as much as it applied to newspapers.
Even if you fail to find any examples of
a disputed use, it’s not dispositive. Some modern corpora don’t contain a
single example of the word “vehicle” being used to refer to an airplane, for
instance.
So when a corpus analysis reveals that a term was used in
a disputed sense X percent of the time, that means . . . what, exactly? At what
cutoff can we confirm or deny that the disputed use is part of the ordinary
meaning? The appropriate thresholds will vary from case to case, often falling
all the way to zero, and reasonable people will disagree as to where they
should be. How often a term is used to describe a given situation depends not
only on the term’s meaning, but also on how common or newsworthy the situation
is, as well as the alternative words that speakers have at their disposal.
This problem is compounded by the fact that corpus
analysis systematically produces narrow senses of what a term means, as a paper in the Harvard Law Review last year
by Kevin P. Tobia showed.
In a series of experiments run on ordinary people, law
students, and judges, Tobia divided his subjects into three groups. One group
was simply given a term (say, “vehicle”) and asked whether various things
counted as part of the category (cars, airplanes, shoulder baby carriers,
etc.), to gauge the scope of the term’s ordinary meaning. The other two groups,
by contrast, were not given the actual word, so they wouldn’t rely
on their preexisting sense of what the word meant. Instead, they were given a
fake word (such as “ailac”), accompanied by either (A) a dictionary definition
of the real word Tobia was testing or (B) some results from a corpus analysis
of that word, including examples of the word used in context and other terms
the word was frequently used alongside.
The upshot of these experiments is that corpus analysis
tends to highlight a narrow subset of a term’s potential uses. Those relying on
corpus results, for example, tended to say that an airplane does not count as a
vehicle (or rather, as an “ailac”), contrary to the folks who were asked to
rely on their own sense of the word. Originalist fans of dictionary definitions
shouldn’t take any comfort in the study, either: Those relying on dictionary
definitions tended to have an especially broad sense of the
tested word, saying, for instance, that a shoulder baby carrier is a vehicle.
In general, Tobia writes, corpus analysis points users to
“prototypical” uses of a given word, while dictionaries provide definitions
broad enough to cover uses that qualify only “technically.” Certainly, it can
be useful for a judge to see a range of plausible options: Sometimes context
will make clear that the word is being used in a narrow or broad way, for
instance, and under the “rule of lenity,” ambiguous laws are supposed to be
read in whatever way favors a criminal defendant. But corpus analysis
does not reveal some hidden, true ordinary meaning of words
that we’ve lacked until now; it just highlights some typical uses.
To this point, you may notice, I’ve focused on problems
with interpreting the results of a corpus analysis, implicitly
assuming that the analysis itself is sound. But lots can also go wrong in the
process that culminates in a computer spitting out results and a researcher
counting them up.
Obviously, no corpus is comprehensive. Those from the
Founding era necessarily include only what was written down, as recording
technology did not exist, and are biased in favor of the elite, male, and white
Americans whose writings are most likely to have survived. In addition, corpus
analysis tends to give all uses of a term equal weight, rather than giving
special consideration to the most on-point examples. If we’re analyzing a
constitutional provision, for instance, we might want to pay extra attention to
uses of the term in that particular context.
And any attempt to “query” these databases and “code” the
results requires a series of judgment calls. Researchers need to pick out
which sets of words they’re looking for, which can include numerous variants of
the term used in the law they’re studying, and they have the option of
searching for examples of a word only when it’s used in close proximity to
others (as a way of looking within a specific context, or of finding variants
of multiple-word terms). They can also exclude uses they think are irrelevant
to the question they’re trying to answer. Then they have to decide which of the
results they kept count as examples of the disputed use, and which don’t.
To be fair, researchers can make all of these decisions
in a very transparent manner, publishing their exact queries, results, coding,
and so on. But this is all an art, not a science.
Interpreting the Second Amendment in Particular
With all that in mind, let’s review what corpus analysis has
actually revealed about the term “bear arms.”
Several analyses suggest that “bear arms” was used
overwhelmingly — though not exclusively — in the military
context in and around the Founding era. In a 2018 Washington Post article, one linguist
announced that only a “handful” out of 1,500 uses he’d found “don’t refer to
war, soldiering or organized, armed action.” A 2019 article in BYU Law Review concluded
that just 4 percent of uses were of the “non-militia/private use”
variety. Yet another 2019 article, published on the SSRN platform, found that
“the corpus data for bear arms was overwhelmingly dominated by
uses of the phrase in its idiomatic military sense.”
For the reasons noted above, it’s not even clear how
devastating or consequential we’re supposed to find this. No one ever denied
that “bearing arms” frequently had a military connotation, and at any rate, the
Second Amendment itself contains that pesky reference to the “militia.” The
question is whether the term, as used, is limited to the
military sense. Scalia even discussed this issue briefly in Heller itself,
though he was more dismissive of some empirical findings than, in retrospect,
he should have been:
Justice Stevens points to a study
by amici supposedly showing that the phrase “bear arms” was
most frequently [i.e., in 110 out of 115 examples] used in the military
context. . . . Of course, as we have said, the fact that the phrase was
commonly used in a particular context does not show that it is limited to that
context, and, in any event, we have given many sources where the phrase was
used in nonmilitary contexts.
Other results reveal additional nuance. A paper by Josh Jones, for example, points out that some
earlier research excluded all uses of “bear arms” in contexts directly related
to the Second Amendment, which are actually the most relevant
uses. Jones further notes that the preponderance of military uses isn’t
surprising in a violent era such as the Founding and that when the term is used
in the military context, it can still be used literally: to refer to carrying
weapons, rather than as an idiom that denotes military activity in general.
Jones provides several examples where “bearing arms” was discussed as just one
of several aspects of military service. When he includes all uses of the term
and divides them into literal vs. idiomatic senses, he finds that between
one-fifth and two-fifths of uses were literal.
Phillips and Blackman have also previewed some results of a corpus analysis, though their final
paper is still forthcoming. On the overall question of who got Heller right,
they are “more convinced by Scalia’s majority opinion than Stevens’s dissent.”
They do find that about 90 percent of uses of “bear arms” and its variants were
military in nature, but they rightly caution that “whether these results show
that the Second Amendment language precludes an individual right is a more
complicated question.” They further point out that when the word “arms” was
used in the key context of rights, individual uses were hardly
rare: “About 40 percent of the results had a militia sense, about 25 percent
used an individual sense, and about 30 percent referred to both militia and
individual senses.”
To go even further into the relevant context, one can
focus specifically on Second Amendment analogues — bearing-arms protections in
state declarations of rights, draft versions of the Second Amendment itself,
etc. Some of these provisions protected the people’s right to bear arms in
defense of themselves and the state; one proposal mentioned
“the purpose of killing game”; and even more restrictive formulations, such as
“bear arms for the common defense,” imply that the term could have a broader
meaning when not so restricted. A brief in the current Supreme Court case by longtime
Second Amendment lawyer David T. Hardy argues that “whatever the most common
use of ‘bear arms’ was in ordinary speech, in constitutional enactments, ‘bear
arms’ was universally understood as protecting defensive carry of ordinary
arms.”
But once we get to that point, we’re back where we
started, with the extensive record that informed the decisions and dissents
in Heller and McDonald. As those cases (and the
copious briefs in the current case) make obvious, there’s a whole lot of
history there that doesn’t take a corpus to analyze. This starts with the English rights that formed the backdrop to American
law. It includes those analogues to the Second Amendment. It runs through the
plain language of the amendment itself and contemporary dictionaries’ definitions of “bear.” It
continues through court decisions and other legal writings in the early
decades of the country, and through events that unfolded well after the
Founding: It was the 14th Amendment, enacted after the Civil War, that applied
federal constitutional protections to the states, and black Americans’ right to bear arms was
frequently discussed in that context.
I won’t wade through all of that again here; there’s no
point when so many others on both sides of the debate already have. I will just
say that if you studied this issue ten years ago and came to have a strong
opinion, the results of the emerging field of corpus analysis should at most
mildly color your view of the topic.
No comments:
Post a Comment