By Jason Lee Steorts
Saturday, May 11, 2024
A war — culture or shooting — is like crack to moral
bullies. They see their opponents as wicked, have little tolerance for
complexity and for ambivalence in response to it, and demand with rhetorical
and sometimes actual violence that others endorse their view. This is
unfortunate, because the questions raised by a war are usually not simple. Nor
are they of a single category: One must take in-principle answers to moral
questions and apply them to complicated and changing factual situations, as
well as to predictions about those situations made conditionally on possible
courses of action. Complexity and ambivalence will be complements of realism.
Welcoming them, I’d like to think about whether the
Israeli campaign against Hamas has been morally justified despite its harms to
noncombatants in the Gaza Strip. I will often be making judgments that are
conditional — “If this is so, then I think that is right,” “If that is so, then
I think this must be wrong” — which should be taken as accurate statement of a
complicated view rather than as a refusal to take one. You may not agree with
my views but, if not, I hope you will disagree in precise ways that clarify
your own — a benefit of disagreement done right.
Not everything is complicated. There is moral bullying
and then there is moral bullying. Some defenders of the war go too far in
casting disagreement as personal failure. But this cannot really be compared to
ripping down posters of Israeli hostages, refusing to let Jews enter buildings
and outdoor spaces on college campuses, and calling for the triumph of Hamas
“from the river to the sea.” Israel has a right to exist and to defend itself.
The Hamas massacres of October 7 (it is good to use the plural because it
forces the imagination to become more specific), the torture and murder of
whole families, the sadistic rapes, the abduction and abuse of hostages — all
of that is as obvious a casus belli as can be imagined. Along with Hamas’s vow
to carry out similar attacks in the future, it justifies Israel in seeking
Hamas’s total destruction. To seek it even seems an obligation of state,
provided that it can be sought at acceptable cost.
The ambiguity we will encounter is foreshadowed in that
final clause. Granted that Israel’s cause is just, what are we to think of its
means, and of the effects those means are having on others than their targets?
Do the killing of large numbers of noncombatants — we must assume the number is
large even if we should take the official Hamas figure with skepticism — and
the lack of food and medicine Gaza render the war unjust in execution even
though its purpose is good?
***
A just war will almost always see the killing of
noncombatants, but it is wrong to kill them on purpose. That insight will be
our ethical North Star. It is an application of what’s known as “double-effect
theory,” a niche of ethics that began with Thomas Aquinas and other medieval
Catholic thinkers and has influenced modern views and law concerning justice in
warfare.
In his famous book Just and Unjust Wars, the
modern classic on the topic, Michael Walzer sums up the conditions that must be
met for an act to be permissible under double-effect theory:
1. The
act [of war] is good in itself or at least indifferent, which means, for our
purposes, that it is a legitimate act of war.
2. The
direct effect is morally acceptable — the destruction of military supplies, for
example, or the killing of enemy soldiers.
3. The
intention of the actor is good, that is, he aims only at the acceptable effect;
the evil [of killing civilians, say] is not one of his ends, nor is it a means
to his ends.
4. The
good effect is sufficiently good to compensate for allowing the evil effect; it
must be justifiable under [Henry] Sidgwick’s proportionality rule, [according
to which one may not do “any mischief which does not tend materially to the end
{of victory}, nor any mischief of which the conduciveness to the end is slight
in comparison with the amount of mischief”].
The first three requirements generalize our intuition
that there will be bad outcomes in a just war but what’s wrong is to seek them.
One seeks only what is “good” or “acceptable”; the “evil” secondary outcome is
outside one’s intentions even if one foresees it. A way of testing this
intuitively is to ask whether one would prevent the evil outcome if one could
do so without forgoing the good one.
Why the detail that one must not seek the evil outcome
as means to one’s just end? This is part of what it is for the
evil effect to be unintended; one intends the end, and therefore one intends
the means to it — and so it will not do, indeed it is a kind of contradiction,
to say “I intend only this good end but not the evil means of achieving it.” In
practice the requirement prevents casual sacrifices of innocents as motivated
by sophistical casuistry. One may not, to borrow a philosophy-class cliché,
throw a man onto rail tracks as one’s means of stopping the train from hitting
some larger number of people. One also may not terrorize a civilian population
into submission to win a war.
The fourth principle is a problem because it is vague.
What amount of mischief is disproportionate, Professor Sidgwick? And how are we
to measure it? Answers will seem artificial and arbitrary if we try to assign
exact amounts of utility and “weigh” outcomes as on a scale. But the
requirement can be interpreted more holistically, as an “on the whole” taking
of everything into account. Nothing depends on Sidgwick or utilitarianism
(Sidgwick was a utilitarian); statements of double-effect theory normally include
some vague total proportionality criterion of this kind, which takes the form
of the writer’s preferred meta-ethics.
I think the fourth principle cannot plausibly mean, for
our purposes, that justice in war requires that one cause fewer deaths than
one’s own side suffers. If terrorists were to kill a hundred civilians and
counterattacking the terrorists killed a thousand, to counterattack would not
therefore be unjust, because it matters that one side is killing civilians
deliberately while the other is trying to stop the first from doing so.
On the other hand, most of us would agree that not any amount
of suffering may be inflicted on people, even if unintendedly, in order to
achieve any legitimate military purpose. It matters how
important the purpose is; it matters, so to speak, that no one burn the world
down while winning a battle.
Here is a standard example to illustrate an act of war
that would easily meet all the double-effect requirements. Suppose there is a
missile factory. Suppose you need to bomb it. You intend to bomb it at night
when a janitor is working there. There is no way to warn him without
endangering the mission. You know that by bombing you will kill him. But you
are not aiming at his death — it is an unfortunate but unsought consequence of
what you must do. You are even trying to minimize such deaths by not bombing during
the day. So it is all right to bomb the factory and kill the janitor.
***
Consider now the Israeli military campaign, and in
particular the highly destructive bombing of targets in urban areas. There is a
strong prima facie case that it satisfies the first three conditions. The war
and its aim — to destroy Hamas — are just. The intended effect of the bombing —
to kill Hamas leaders and fighters and to destroy Hamas’s underground tunnel
network — is legitimate. And I think there is no good evidence that Israel
intends the deaths of noncombatants as either means or end.
A case can even be made that Israel has met a stricter
form of the third requirement than has been traditional. Walzer, concerned that
the standard version justifies too much, adds the portion I have italicized:
3. The
intention of the actor is good, that is, he aims narrowly at the acceptable
effect; the evil effect is not one of his ends, nor is it a means to his
ends; and, aware of the evil involved, he seeks to minimize it,
accepting costs to himself.
Israel has tried to minimize the evil effect of harming
noncombatants by warning them in advance of attacks — something that presumably
reduces the element of surprise and involves the use of time, money, and
equipment for purposes other than military victory.
It has not been easy or even always possible for Gazans
to flee, given the damage to roads and other infrastructure, the difficulty and
expense of finding transportation, the overall chaos of the war, and Hamas’s
contrary demand that everyone remain in place. But it is hard to see how such
problems could have been prevented if a large-scale bombing campaign was to be
conducted at all. Walzer reports that Maimonides counseled besieging a city on
three of its four sides and pronounces this absurd (since it is no longer a
siege). But it is not the worst description of what Israel has tried to do as
it has bombed and invaded Gaza, nor can the attempt be dismissed as an
absurdity.
Israel has been criticized for not using smaller or more
precision-guided ordnance, or simply refraining from bombing in certain areas.
Some of those criticisms have come from the Biden administration, which has
noted occasions in the Middle East when the United States fought with more
restraint. In the early days of the war, Israel’s air-force chief, Brigadier
General Omer Tishler, said that “there is always a military target, but we
are not being surgical.” This could be taken as a simple refusal to “minimize”
the “evil involved” and an argument for the Biden administration’s position.
But it could also reflect an elevated sense of the urgency of the military goal
and a consequently higher tolerance for civilian casualties. If, after October
7, it is more important to destroy underground tunnels and kill Hamas fighters
and leaders without delay, then the use of large bombs, and bombs dropped in
crowded areas (which have been warned), may be closer to a necessity.
That is an important point: the relationship between
double-effect requirements and the perception of necessity. What counts as a
good-enough effort at harm reduction, just like what counts as a proportionate
“on the whole” cost, depends on our prior conclusions about the importance of
the military goal. The mischief of double-effect theory when it justifies too
much usually comes from a false belief that we simply have to
go do this or that disturbing thing and therefore, very sadly, must tolerate
the evil consequences of doing it. The motivating force all comes from the
judgment of necessity. So we had better get it right, lest what seemed a
regrettable side effect turn out to be a sin.
Some argue that Israel’s military goal — to destroy Hamas
— is unachievable. If this were true then the campaign could not be necessary,
since what is impossible can hardly be required. Reports of new Hamas fighters
in northern Gaza and the recent launching thence of Hamas rockets have been
cited in support of such an argument. But this is to be too literal about the
meaning of “destroy.” Israel may not be able to neutralize every Hamas cell in
such a way that no new attacks will happen. It nonetheless is good that Israel
attack as many Hamas fighters as it can and weaken the organization as much as
possible.
There is also, however, a way of being less literal about
the idea that the war goal is impossible. It is to think that the destruction
of Hamas will have to have a diplomatic component, will happen somewhat
gradually, and will involve in some measure a reduction of the group to
irrelevance rather than its complete military destruction. In the early days of
the war, former Israeli prime minister Naftali Bennet — no political
progressive — outlined for New York Times columnist Bret
Stephens a plan to sideline Hamas that would not have seen a large-scale ground
invasion or a massive bombing campaign, but rather the creation of a buffer
zone, the use of special-forces raids, and an eventual exile of some of Hamas’s
political leadership to a state that would have them. This, Bennet maintained,
would be more realistic as strategy and would not turn world sympathy against
Israel.
One feels the possibility of tragedy in our inability to
know whether Bennet was right. But I don’t think that this lack of certainty
warrants us to conclude that Israel’s actual strategy has been wrong. The
judgment that large-scale bombing and invasion were necessary seems at least
reasonable: It is possible to see the strategy as necessary. To say that
it must necessarily be seen as necessary would be to set a
very high bar.
Something similar goes for the idea of relying more on
special-forces raids. Walzer cites the Vemork raid in World War II, in which
the Allies destroyed a heavy-water plant in Nazi-occupied Norway, as compliant
with his revision of the third requirement. Rather than bomb the plant, which
would have killed many civilians, a special-forces team was dispatched to
destroy it. The first effort failed and the special forces were all killed. The
second effort succeeded. Certainly the raid was heroic. But it seems wrong to
say that bombing the plant would have been wrong, given the stakes. And
regardless, as Walzer notes, one cannot fight a whole war of Vemork raids. That
applies also in Gaza if, again, something like the Bennet plan was not going to
be followed. We might criticize targeting decisions, but if bombing and
invasion are plausibly necessary, then criticisms should be circumscribed to
the execution of that strategy and exclude demands for a different one.
***
It is necessary, however, to reassess what is permissible
in relation to a goal if the costs of pursuing the goal become too high. One
cannot really know the cost of a military goal in advance, since one cannot
really predict the course of a war. Urgent recently has been the question
whether Israel should bombard and invade Rafah, in southern Gaza, in order to
kill the remaining thousands of Hamas fighters and destroy the large
underground tunnel complex there. It has already instructed some hundred thousand
people to evacuate the city, and air strikes and ground fighting have begun.
The returns on killing common fighters by bombing and
invading urban areas can be expected to diminish the more fighters have been
killed, even as the reputational damage to Israel rises with the number of
noncombatant deaths. Since Israel depends on alliances with and sympathy from
other states, an outcry over the death toll must be considered a matter of
strategic concern for it. The concern is also moral; as we said above, justice
in a warfare is not a simple matter of which side kills fewer people, but the
amount of mischief still does grow with the civilian death toll. Whatever our
precise judgment, we should all want the campaign to become more surgical if it
can.
There is also now a risk of famine, or already an
incipient famine, throughout Gaza. Whether it has begun is disputed, but it is
not reasonably in dispute that Gaza cannot feed itself and that widespread
death from malnutrition and attendant disease is imminent if large amounts of
food aid and medicine are not distributed soon.
Early in the war, Israeli defense minister Yoav Gallant
said that no food would go into Gaza until the hostages came out — a threat of
an act that would clearly violate double-effect requirements. But actual
Israeli policy before the Rafah fighting began had contradicted his statement,
by consistently seeking to increase food aid (for example, by opening more
border crossings and endorsing a U.S. plan to build a pier on the Mediterranean
for the delivery of aid by boat). The food and medicine massed along the Gazan
border had not been distributed effectively for various reasons: delays
inherent in Israeli inspections (to ensure that prohibited items were not
smuggled to Hamas), looting of aid convoys (by Hamas fighters among others),
road damage, and combat. Since the Rafah fighting began, however, almost no aid
has gone in at all, because Israel has closed the most important crossing while
Egypt has inexcusably declined to let food trucks enter through a different
one.
Israel will not have intended a famine if one does occur,
which is to say Israel will have satisfied the original three
requirements of double-effect theory as quoted above. It nonetheless seems
wrong in all but the most exceptional circumstances to use methods that,
predictably, will trigger a famine — and even if other parties are also
casually and morally responsible for its occurrence (as Egypt and Hamas are in
Gaza). To say this is not to claim that Israel should offer a permanent
cease-fire and give up the goal of destroying Hamas militarily. It is only to
say that, however the war continues, it must not continue in a way that causes
the noncombatant population to starve.
To knowingly trigger a famine would of course violate
Walzer’s revised third requirement: It would involve accepting
rather than minimizing a catastrophic harm to civilians who could not, as with
the bombings, be directed to flee. The logic of besieging a city on three sides
does not apply to a famine.
Not all will accept Walzer’s revision, but there is also
the original fourth requirement: to do on the whole proportionately more good
than evil. It is hard to see how the excruciating cost of a famine, in both
moral and strategic terms, would be worth the marginal benefit of killing the
few remaining battalions of common Hamas fighters. Leaders of the organization
are known and can be targeted opportunistically at a later time, as can tunnels
be bombed. Common fighters may disperse but will not be effective without
leadership and organization, and can perhaps also be targeted later.
My claim is not that, in principle, one may never trigger
a famine (strange thing to consider; rarely discussed in advice columns). But
again I would refocus discussion on the questions of necessity and certainty.
If for whatever reason the only way to prevent a nuclear attack were to invade
the prospective attacker’s territory in a manner that would cause a famine
there, and if one were certain or close to it that no other method could
prevent the attack, then I think one would have to invade and regret the
famine. Similarly, if we had very strong reasons to think that Israel’s
survival, or even the prevention of more October 7 massacres, required military
activities that would cause a famine, then I would consider the famine a tragic
necessity. But I do not think such a connection has been shown clearly enough
to justify such a course now. Nor do I think that the remaining Israeli
hostages will fare well as food runs out.
Notice how our moral and factual uncertainties rise with
each statement: (1) Israel has a right to exist and defend itself and
its people, and therefore, given October 7, it should seek to destroy Hamas and
rescue the hostages. (2) A large-scale bombing and ground invasion is part of
the best strategy for destroying Hamas and rescuing the hostages. (3) The
pursuit of those goals requires that the campaign be continued right now rather
than postponed for any length of time, even if continuing it now will trigger a
famine. The moral and rhetorical force of (1) does not transfer all
the way to (3). It diminishes, in the style of multiplying denominators, at
each step along the way.
This observation helps give form to the fourth
requirement, that one not do too much mischief in relation to the good to be
achieved. This should not mean that Israel must accept more October Sevenths as
preferable to famine in Gaza if that definite choice is put to it. It should
mean that the immediate continuation of the war cannot be connected so clearly
to the prevention of another October 7 as to make famine an acceptable cost. It
looks like burning a world down speculatively.
Of course, we have been assuming that famine is sure to
follow the continuation of the campaign and can be prevented otherwise. Perhaps
that is false. But the moral risk of uncertainty goes both ways. It would be
correct and tidy to say that continuing a strategy becomes wrong at just the
point where we know that doing so will cause a famine. But it may not be
possible to identify that point. Responsibility and blame therefore apply in a
probabilistic way, so that to risk a famine is more wrong the smaller one’s
margin of error and the lower one’s certainty as to the need for acts that
might cause the famine. An obligation exists not to be reckless, and it rises
with the magnitude of the risk.
***
Let me end by considering two kinds of objections that
seem like natural replies to the arguments I have made.
The first acknowledges that the harms to noncombatants
are atrocious but assigns responsibility for the atrocity to Hamas alone. It
is, after all, Hamas that prolongs the war by not surrendering, Hamas that
started the war by committing acts worthy of Satan. Hamas routinely uses
noncombatants as human shields; it commands Gazans not to flee combat zones; it
hides tunnels and weapons beneath hospitals and mosques and schools; it abducts
and abuses and kills hostages; it loots food trucks; it fights without uniform.
Surely whatever harm comes to Gazans is Hamas’s fault, not Israel’s.
It is true that Hamas is guilty of all those things;
there really is no defending it. And it’s true that all harms to noncombatants
would end if only Hamas abandoned its wicked cause, freed its hostages, and
surrendered. But from this it cannot follow that concerns about the suffering
of noncombatant Palestinians no longer apply, because the duty to refrain from
harming them unjustly is owed directly to them. While the choices Hamas makes
do place the burden of civilian casualties on it in some contexts (as when
human shields are killed in necessary attacks), and do justly affect how Hamas
fighters themselves may be treated (they are not owed Geneva protections, for
instance), those choices do not decide in general how much Israel should care
about civilians in Gaza: The human shields are on Hamas, but there are also the
people in the building next door. And it changes nothing that Gazans elected
Hamas as their government or that some four in five Palestinians endorse the
October 7 attacks. A terrible choice and a terrible view, but civilized nations
do not kill people for how they vote or what they think.
Consider again that whether one fights with just means is
a separate matter from whether one’s cause is just. It will usually be true in
a war that one side’s cause is just while the other’s is not, or at least that
some side has more justice than any other; but if this means that the party
with justice behind it may simply do whatever it likes and hang the pain of
noncombatants around the neck of an enemy government, then not even massacres
will be ruled out. And once we do adopt principles that imply limits to the
conduct of war, we will have to apply them to each individual strategy or
tactic. We cannot refrain from self-judgment simply because Hamas and its
purpose, unlike Israel, are barbaric.
The second sort of objection appeals to history. Sieges
and blockades and even attacks on civilians have been part of warfare since
antiquity. The Union blockaded the Confederacy and Britain blockaded Wilhelmine
Germany. The Allies in World War II went so far as to massacre civilians from
the air in order to demoralize Germany and Japan.
Double-effect theory cannot be right if the firebombing
of Tokyo and the dropping of atomic bombs (in preference to accepting a
conditional surrender) were right. But I’ll stick with double-effect theory.
Massacring civilians is wrong even in a just cause, and it’s good that doing so
is less accepted now than it was 80 years ago. This is not to concede, however,
that opposition to such methods is a newfangled idea. Thomas Aquinas would
certainly have had to be horrified by Hiroshima if he had been around to apply
his ethics consistently in 1945. As for the practice of warfare in antiquity,
it is best approached as a museum of the abhorrent. Not that this especially
matters, since the fact that something has been done is not a reason to keep
doing it. History absolves posterity of nothing.
Sieges are now prohibited under the Geneva Conventions
(as necessarily targeting noncombatants) while blockades are not. The Israeli
policy in Gaza is neither precisely a siege nor precisely a blockade. But the
blockades in the Civil War and World War I are worth considering as contrasts
with the Gazan situation.
A defense of the Union and British policies can be found
in “Noncombatant Immunity and the Ethics of Blockade,” a 2019 paper by Robert
Mayer (available online). Mayer thinks that it is always wrong to starve
civilians on purpose, but he does not think that that is what the British and
the Union were up to. Germany had enough food to keep the whole population
alive if only it had rationed more equitably. The British therefore did no more
than force the German government “to choose between providing for [all] its
people and maximizing its military might [by giving larger rations to
soldiers].” The German government chose badly, and the ensuing deaths were on
it. Similarly for the North’s blockade of the South: The purpose of the
blockade was to make life harder for the Confederacy and prevent the sale of
cash crops, but the blockade did not starve anyone. If people starved, it was
because of Sherman going berserk and similarly colorful episodes.
Mayer’s argument generalizes, then, as the idea that
blockade is justifiable only insofar as it compels hard choices about the
allocation of resources; it should not be done if the blockading power knows
that the blockade will make people starve. This of course raises the problem we
mentioned above of not being able to identify a tipping point. Mayer’s position
depends on the possibility of seeing that there is enough food to go
around, but that certainty will often be elusive. When it is, the line between
forcing hard choices and starving civilians to death collapses into a
probabilistic willingness to commit slow-motion massacre (or, if you prefer,
a merely probabilistic determination not to).
For our purposes, though, what is most important to see
are two things. On one hand, the intention of Israel is better than that of the
Union or the British; it is not trying to use hunger as a weapon (even one
aimed only at forcing hard choices). But on the other hand, and to me
dispositively, the situation of Gaza is not like that of Germany or the
Confederacy. It is like that of Yemen. Yemen has in recent years suffered
famine in consequence of a Saudi-led blockade of the Houthis. Discussing that
blockade, Mayer wrote that it “should be acceptable for a short period at most”
since Yemen is not self-sufficient in food, and that, “in such cases, fault for
the starvation that ensues must be assigned to the blockading force, because it
is not feasible for the local authorities to feed their own people.”
No comments:
Post a Comment