By Jonah Goldberg
Friday, February 23, 2024
So I’m going to do something a little different today.
Before I explain what I’m doing, I’ll explain the why.
I’ve been writing a lot about Conservatism 101 stuff over
the last year or so because a lot of folks have liberated themselves from what
it actually is—or was (I’m sure we’ll see lots of examples of that at CPAC this
weekend). Well, a key part of this Great Forgetting is nationalism. The
Economist’s cover story this
week is about the need to take “national conservatism” seriously. (To be clear,
they don’t like it. But they also think it’s not going away.) Nationalism is
being sold by some as an alternative to conservatism and by others not as a
replacement but as the “true” conservatism. They often sound like nationalism
is some prince-in-exile who needs to be restored to the throne. Nationalism is
the forgotten, authentic, or “true” conservatism.
I think this is nonsense.
But I think confusion over nationalism extends beyond
various quarters of the right. Here,
for example, Politico’s democracy reporter Heidi Przybyla (who I like
personally), makes the bizarre claim that if you think your rights come from
God, you’re a “Christian nationalist.” I will audition for the annual World’s
Biggest Understatement Award and simply say that this claim is … contestable.
Meanwhile, the anti-Israel left has all manner of weird notions about
nationalism, starting with the idea that a territory or region called by the
Romans “Palestine” (as a way to snub the Jews) was actually a country that
existed there before Israel and was a Jew-free country before 1948. (Spoiler:
It was neither Jew-free nor a country, and Israel was there first.) And, of
course, Vladimir Putin and his fans have all manner of very hot takes on what
nations are and what nationalism means.
So I want simply to clarify what nationalism is—and
isn’t. Or at least clarify my own understanding of it. So I’m going to make a
down payment on explaining some basic concepts, at least as I see them. If
you’re not in the mood for such eggheady spelunking, that’s cool. I’ll talk to
you next week.
I’ll start by asking a question: When does
a country become a nation?
This might sound like a nonsense question, like “what’s
the difference between a car and an automobile?” That’s because in everyday
conversation, we use the two words interchangeably.
But if we’re going to be precise, there’s a real
difference. A country is an area of land with a single government. A nation is
a relatively coherent group of people who share a culture, language, ethnicity,
or sense of common fate. The “Kurdish nation” is a thing, but the Kurds have no
country (semiautonomous Iraqi Kurdistan notwithstanding). Scotland and England
are two nations in one country. The nation of England is much
older than the country of England. The “Heptarchy” of Anglo-Saxon
England was made up of seven kingdoms (East Anglia, Essex, Kent, Mercia, Northumbria, Sussex, and Wessex) until that was
consolidated into four kingdoms in the eighth century. In 927, England became a
unitary country under Æthelstan.
Again, terminology can get messy. But today we usually
refer to countries as nation-states—the nation part describes the people, the
state part describes the government. But technically speaking, not all
countries are nation-states. The oldest form of polity—outside of clans,
tribes, troops, etc.—are city-states. The ancient world was full of somewhat
identifiable nations that were divided up into city-states: Uruk, Ur, Thebes,
Memphis, and, of course Rome, come to mind. But more to the point, we still have
some city-states—Monaco, Singapore, and the Vatican are independent city-states
or countries, but they are not nation-states.
In short, it is important to keep in mind that the nation-state is
a relatively recent invention, while the nation is much older.
Indeed, most
nation-states are pretty young.
You can meaningfully talk about the Greek nation going
back thousands of years. But Greece didn’t become a formal and sovereign
nation-state until 1832. Belgium, where Julius Caesar faced some of his most
fierce opposition (“Of all the Gauls,” Caesar famously said “the Belgians are
the bravest enemies I have ever faced”) became a country two years earlier, in
1830. Indeed, if you look at a map of Europe in the 1830s,
the number of recognizable independent nations is comparatively small. There’s
France, Spain, England and a few more. But there are no independent
nation-states of Germany, Austria, Poland, Slovakia, Czechia, Bosnia, Romania,
or Ukraine (then controlled by the Hapsburgs and Russians). Germany until the
19th century was a nation, but not a nation-state. It was chock-a-block with
various little independent kingdoms and “states.” Russia and Austria-Hungary
were “countries” or “states” but they were composed of near-countless nations
or countries.
In 1946 there were 36
nations in the United Nations. By 1970 the number was 127. The roster
didn’t expand nearly fourfold because a bunch of old countries decided to join
the club for all the perks. Most became members once they became countries.
This is one of the ironies of anti-colonialism. Lots of “post-colonial
“countries are products of colonialism—i.e. many colonies were
transformed into countries by their colonizers who created within them a sense
of nationhood that hadn’t existed before. There’s a school of thought that the
British created India. “India is a geographical term,”
Churchill once said. “It is no more a united nation than the equator.” There’s
a lot of debate about all that, but suffice it to say, there’s some truth
to the idea.
What makes all of this even more otherworldly to the
contemporary mind is that pretty much all of these countries, empires, and
nation-states until very recently didn’t “belong” to the people. They belonged
to a network of families, or dynasties, which operated a lot like the Mafia.
Each family had its territory. Some of these territories had been in the family
for centuries. But the families were constantly looking to acquire more
territory, often through war, but sometimes through marriage or barter (and usually
the marriages were a form of sealing the deal of the barter). For millennia,
the authority of royal dynasties derived from the fact that they descended from
some warlord. This is what Albert Jay Nock was getting at when he said, “The
State’s criminality is nothing new and nothing to be wondered at,” he wrote.
“It began when the first predatory group of men clustered together and formed
the State, and it will continue as long as the State exists in the world,
because the State is fundamentally an anti-social institution, fundamentally
criminal. The idea that the State originated to serve any kind of social
purpose is completely unhistorical. It originated in conquest and
confiscation—that is to say, in crime.”
Anyway, the argument that “nationalism” is some ancient,
natural, form of social organization is not very powerful. It’s not entirely
wrong, either. But it depends on a lot of historical cherry-picking. Yoram
Hazony, if memory serves, claims that the idea of the nation-state comes from
Israel and then is super-charged after the Protestant Reformation. Okay, maybe.
Why not? But also, so what? There’s a lot of history between ancient Israel and
the 1600s, and very little of it supports the claim that the idea of
nationalism—or even what you might call nation-ism (which is what I think
Hazony often really means)—was very powerful. Certainly, all of those nations
were still the playthings of kings and nobles.
Actual nationalism starts in the late 1700s in America—a
pretty unique case—but really with the French Revolution. And it’s been
unfolding ever since. Earlier I noted the irony of colonial powers creating
anti-colonial new nations. That, after all, is the story of America. It took a
long time for the founding generation to see itself as something other than
British. If King George had respected their claims to their “ancient British
rights and liberties,” it’s doubtful the United States would have become a nation,
at least not for a long time.
German nationalism is a more relevant example. It was
basically ignited by the French Revolutionary and Napoleonic occupiers who
aroused a sense of nationhood among the disparate German people. Interestingly,
to me at least, the first German nationalists weren’t really
ethno-nationalists—race science was in its infancy back then—but linguistic nationalists.
Vladimir Putin’s nationalism often looks a lot like this. He talks about all
Russian speakers, including in the Baltics and elsewhere, as if they are simply
Russians.
Indeed, Palestinian nationalism—and one day nationhood—is
entirely a product of Israel’s existence. Had there been no Israel in 1948,
“the Palestinians” would be Arabs living in Egypt, Jordan, etc.
Today, largely because of the atrophied vocabulary of
contemporary politics, nationalism is cast as the opposite of liberalism. But
that’s not how it worked. The age of nationalism was also the age of democracy
and the age of liberalism. America’s Founders were nationalists, they were also
liberals. Even in Europe, many—maybe even most—of the original nationalists
were to one extent or other liberal in the classical sense (and in fairness to
Hazony, despite his weird hatred of liberal theory, in practice
he’s still a liberal in that he’s for democracy and the rule of law and all
that stuff). Some liberal nationalists wanted democracy or “republicanism,”
while others just wanted the rule of law, free speech, a free press, and the
protection of property rights etc. Others didn’t care much about that stuff,
preferring instead to restore the sovereignty of their own royal rulers.
However, what united all of them, to one extent or another, was the idea their
nation should be its own country. Bohemia for the Bohemians and that kind of
thing.
This brings us to another term that needs to be
illuminated: “popular sovereignty.” This is the idea that the people are the
real owners of the country they live in (of course, who counts as “the people”
can be an ugly question—just ask the Jews, Rohingya, Uyghurs, et al). Today
popular sovereignty and democracy are pretty much synonymous, but that’s not
how it started. Initially, democracy—often called republicanism, but that gets
complicated too—was just one form of popular sovereignty.
During the 1800s there were plenty of nationalists whose
idea of popular sovereignty meant being ruled by their own king or parliament
of nobles, not some foreign ruler. Think of it this way: In Braveheart,
Mel Gibson talks a lot about “freedom,” but he isn’t talking at all about
democracy—he’s talking about national liberation. Popular sovereignty could
mean democracy or republicanism, but it could just as easily mean, “We want one
of our own to rule us.” Woodrow Wilson’s call for “self-determination” is often
used by his apologists to suggest he favored democracy for everybody. But he
didn’t. It could mean democracy, but it could also mean that empires be broken
up into sovereign nation-states that governed themselves as they saw fit.
This thinking is alive and well today, by the way. Lots
of apologists for Hamas, Iran, Russia, China, Saudi Arabia, et al., often talk
as if illiberal tyranny is just an authentic expression of these non-Western
cultures and who are we to judge them, never mind impose our ideas on
them?
So while all nationalists believe in popular sovereignty,
not all nationalists believe in democracy. Adolf Hitler was a nationalist, he
didn’t have much use for democracy. Even Stalin, a Georgian and promoter of
international socialism, became a Soviet and a really Russian nationalist once
in power. Nationalists, contrary to Hazony’s claims, can also be imperialists.
Hitler wanted “Ein Volk, ein Reich, ein Führer,” but he also wanted to
subjugate inferior peoples’ and nations. Xi Jinping is a nationalist and an
imperialist; just ask the Tibetans and Uyghurs.
This raises another distinction. Hitler and Xi are
ethnonationalists. Lots of liberal nationalists take great pains to
insist—often accurately and rightly—that they are not ethno-nationalists.
Liberal nationalists still believe in liberal democracy, to one extent or
another. Ethnonationalists believe that the nation rightfully belongs to a
single ethnicity, variously defined. Hitler’s nationalism was reserved for
Germans (or Teutons or Aryans), Xi’s nationalism is less extreme, but he is a
practitioner of Han supremacy. Mussolini was not an ethnonationalist, but he
wasn’t a liberal nationalist either. Rather, he was a cultural nationalist.
Biological racism is a poor fit for an ethnically polyglot country like
Italy.
To the extent you can call Israel “nationalist,” it is
also liberal. Claims that it is ethnonationalist fall apart when you consider
that it is a very multiethnic country, with citizens of every hue and faith.
The freest Arabs in the Middle East are Arab-Israeli citizens. The Jews of
Israel, meanwhile, come from Europe, but also North Africa and elsewhere in the
Middle East. Critics like to erase these inconvenient facts by insisting that
the country is comprised of settler-colonial oppressors from Europe. But the
majority aren’t of European descent. And the supermajority are Sabras—Israelis
who were born in Israel. If you want to say it’s a religiously nationalist
country, that’s a defensible claim. But you should acknowledge that its
liberalism is a profound check on this aspect of its character. Israel is far
more religiously tolerant than most of its neighbors.
I’ve thrown a lot of terminological distinctions at you.
But there’s a false distinction I should address as well. The communist left in
the 1920s and 1930s insisted that “nationalism” and “socialism” are opposites.
This claim was rooted in the Soviet Union’s desire to have an uncontested
monopoly on the concept and implementation of socialism. With the help of
pronouncements like Stalin’s “Theory
of Social Fascism,” the left claimed that any socialist movement that
wasn’t loyal to Moscow, was “right-wing.” Sometimes they used the term
“right-wing socialism.” With the rise of fascism and German national-socialism,
this often got whittled down to “right-wing” or “nationalist.”
But in practice, extreme nationalist regimes were also
socialist, and extreme socialist regimes inevitably became nationalist. Castro
was a socialist. He was also a nationalist. Stalin was once an international
socialist, but in order to stay in power he became a national-socialist
(“socialism in one country,” “great patriotic war for mother Russia,” etc.).
This is because socialism, like nationalism, has the same core logic. Any
hindrance to the good of the collective, the people, the nation, is illegitimate.
And therefore, for the good of the people, the state must have control of the
means of production and the distribution of that product to ensure all of the
people benefit. The distinction between socialism and nationalism on the ground
is about marketing, not principle. Socialized medicine is nationalized health
care.
This false distinction endures to this day, albeit in
watered down form. I chuckle at the avowed nationalists of the right who rail
against the “socialists” of the left, and vice versa, even as their proposed
policies sound awfully similar. Elizabeth Warren’s version of economic justice
looks a lot like various notions of “common good conservatism.” The
distinctions between these combatants on either side of the horseshoe have less
to do with policy or principle and more to do with which team can claim the power
of Tribune of the People.
Let’s talk about today’s version(s) of nationalism. My
first objection to nationalism is that absent qualifiers—like “liberal” or
“benign”—nationalism (again like socialism) has no limiting principle.
Nationalism purports to be concerned with what is good for “the nation.” Sounds
good. But who defines good? One answer, not surprisingly offered by nationalist
populists, is “the people.” But this is rhetorical mischief. Which people? What
if the people are wrong? What if “the people” isn’t everyone but just a faction
of the people? Liberal democracy has answers to these questions. That’s why the
least offensive form of socialism is social democracy—because it concedes that
socialism needs to be curtailed and constrained by democracy. I rarely hear
nationalists make a similar concession.
Unqualified nationalism makes no such concessions. That’s
why non-liberal nationalist systems almost invariably become statist,
socialist, or dictatorial. Because the state or “the leader” ends up being the
only legitimate expression of the will of the people. When the leader does
things that lots of people object to, the leader insists that those people do
not have the nation’s authentic interests at heart. When the legislature or the
courts do something the leader doesn’t want, the leader insists they are
corrupt in some way. The logic of nationalism, absent legal or constitutional
guardrails, leads almost inexorably to the claim that one person is the true
expression of the Nation or the People. This is why I have always seen
nationalism as a modern-sounding backdoor to a kind of monarchism. After all,
this was the objection made by royalists in the face of rising notions of
popular sovereignty: The king knows best what is best for the people. That is
the argument made by Putin, Xi, Hitler, Mussolini, and the countless czars,
emperors, kings, and Caesars deposed by nationalism.
This is why I maintain that patriotism and nationalism
are different things. I am aware that this can be a forced distinction
etymologically, so I’ll put it this way: If patriotism doesn’t mean what I
think it means, we need a word to mean what I mean by patriotism. Nationalism
is an unfettered mystical claim about abstract concepts like “the people” or
“the nation”—ill-suited for a multiethnic, religiously and culturally diverse
liberal democratic nation grounded in a republican constitution. Meanwhile, patriotism,
by my understanding, means fidelity to precisely these liberal and
constitutional commitments. An American nationalist can—and often does—see the
constitutional order as an impediment to the national will and therefore argue
for overturning it or ignoring it. The patriot is loyal to that constitutional
order and the ideals that inform it.
I know I’ve gone very long here. But I need to answer the
question I started with: When does a nation become a country? My short answer
is, when it successfully stands up a government that is recognized by the
people, and later by other countries. (I’d like to say, when it democratically
stands up a government, but democracy is not essential here.)
Which brings me to Ukraine and the treason of the
nationalists.
In Putin’s tirades about Ukraine, he makes it clear that
he subscribes to a pre-nationalist, pre-popular sovereignty, pre-modern theory
of politics. He thinks that because Ukraine wasn’t a country in the ninth or
13th century it can’t be a country today—at least not if he doesn’t want it to
be.
This is contrary to everything nationalists today claim
to believe. And that is what is so disgusting about Putin’s purportedly
nationalist amen choir. Putin is not a nationalist, he’s an imperialist. But
the contemporary nationalists who wax righteous about rejecting the
“imperialism” of the globalists and their institutions—the U.N., the EU, the
World Bank, Davos, whatever—either cheer, mumble pro-forma objections, or
simply stare at their shoes in silence as Putin attempts to erase a sovereign
nation. The Ukrainians have their own language, their own culture, their own
national history, and have been a nation for centuries. What they want to be is
a country. And the allegedly nationalist Putinphiles are too
ignorant or sycophantic to respect that desire because it conflicts with the
ambition of a mass murderer and tyrant.
Putin’s apologists demonstrate that the real point of
nationalism is the pursuit of power. Ideological nationalism is an attempt to
provide a permission structure, to construct the slipperiest slope possible to
their attainment of power. Nationalism, like “post-liberalism,” is an
intellectual pretext, a means toward an end: power. After all, Putin is
trampling every laudatory, beneficial, positive, historical aspect of
nationalism—national and popular sovereignty, democracy, liberalism, etc.—but
because he’s powerful (in their eyes) that’s okay. Because their nationalism
was never really about nationalism; it was about power worship, at home, and
abroad.
No comments:
Post a Comment