By George Will
Saturday, April 22, 2018
Last week, one week after the first anniversary of Neil
Gorsuch’s ascension to the Supreme Court, he delivered an opinion that was
excellent as it pertained to the case at issue and momentous in its
implications pertaining to the institutional tangle known as the administrative
state. If he can persuade his fellow court conservatives to see why they were
mistaken in disagreeing with him, and if he can persuade his liberal colleagues
to follow the logic of their decision with which he concurred, the judiciary
will begin restoring constitutional equilibrium. It will limit Congress’s
imprecise legislating that requires excessive unguided improvising by all those
involved in seeing that the laws are “faithfully” executed.
In 1992, when James Dimaya, a Philippine citizen, was 13,
he became a lawful permanent resident of the United States, where,
unfortunately, his behavior has been less than lawful: In 2007 and 2009, he was
convicted of residential burglary. The Department of Homeland Security says he
should be deported because he committed a “crime of violence,” hence covered by
a portion of immigration law that, after listing specific crimes (rape, murder,
etc.), adds a catch-all category of crimes involving “a substantial risk that
physical force against the person or property of another may be used in the
course of committing the offense.” How are judges supposed to apply this?
Writing for the majority in a 5–4 decision — and joined
by Ruth Bader Ginsburg, Stephen Breyer, and Sonia Sotomayor (with Gorsuch
concurring in the judgment and much of the opinion) — Elena Kagan wrote: The
law’s category, a “crime of violence,” is so indeterminate (“fuzzy,” she said)
that deporting Dimaya under it would violate the Constitution’s “due process of
law” guarantee. Vague laws beget two evils that are related: They do not give
citizens reasonably clear notice of what behavior is proscribed or prescribed.
And they give — actually, require of — judges and law-enforcement officials
excessive discretion in improvising a fuzzy law’s meaning. In agreeing with
this (and disagreeing with John Roberts, Anthony Kennedy, Clarence Thomas, and
Samuel Alito), Gorsuch wrote:
Vague laws “invite the exercise of arbitrary power” by
“leaving the people in the dark about what the law demands and allowing
prosecutors and courts to make it up.” The lack of “precise and sufficient
certainty” (criteria stipulated by the English jurist William Blackstone, whose
writings influenced the Constitution’s Framers) invites “more unpredictability
and arbitrariness” than is constitutional. Furthermore, the crux of America’s
constitutional architecture, the separation of powers, is implicated. All
legislative power is vested in Congress. The judicial power, Gorsuch wrote, “does
not license judges to craft new laws” but only to discern and follow an
existing law’s prescribed course. With the fuzzy “crime of violence” category,
Congress abdicated its “responsibilities for setting the standards of the
criminal law.” So, allowing vague laws would allow Congress “to hand off the
job of lawmaking.” Hence such laws not only illegitimately transfer power to
police and prosecutors but also would “leave it all to a judicial hunch.”
The principle Gorsuch enunciates here regarding one
provision of immigration law is a scythe sharp enough to slice through many
practices of the administrative state, which translates often vague
congressional sentiments into binding rules, a practice indistinguishable from
legislating. Gorsuch’s principle is also pertinent to something pernicious
concerning which he has hitherto expressed wholesome skepticism: “Chevron
deference.”
This is the policy (named for the 1984 case in which the
Supreme Court propounded it) whereby courts are required to defer to
administrative agencies’ interpretations of “ambiguous” laws when the
interpretations are “reasonable.” Gorsuch has criticized this emancipation of
the administrative state from judicial supervision as “a judge-made doctrine
for the abdication of judicial duty.” It also is an incentive for slovenly
lawmaking by a Congress too lazy or risk-averse to be precise in making policy
choices, and so lacking in institutional pride that it complacently sloughs off
its Article I powers onto Article II entities. Gorsuch wants Article III courts
to circumscribe this disreputable behavior.
Gorsuch represents the growing ascendency of one kind of
conservative jurisprudence, “judicial engagement,” over another kind, “judicial
deference.” Many conservatives have embraced populism where it least belongs,
in judicial reasoning. They have advocated broad judicial deference to
decisions because they emanate from majoritarian institutions and processes.
Progressives favor such deference because it liberates executive power from
congressional direction or judicial supervision. Gorsuch, a thinking person’s
conservative, declines to be complicit in this, which raises this question:
When has a progressive justice provided the fifth vote joining four
conservative colleagues?
No comments:
Post a Comment