By Yuval Levin
Wednesday, April 09, 2014
The last few days have provided both a good laugh and
some food for thought on the important question of confirmation bias—people’s
tendency to favor information that confirms their pre-existing views and ignore
information that contradicts those views. It’s a subject well worth some
reflection.
The laugh came from a familiar source. Without (it seems)
a hint of irony, Paul Krugman argued on Monday that everyone is subject to
confirmation bias except for people who agree with him. He was responding to
anessay Ezra Klein wrote for his newly launched site, Vox.com, which took up
the question of confirmation bias and the challenges it poses to democratic
politics. Krugman acknowledged the research that Klein cites but then insisted
that his own experience suggests it is actually mostly people he disagrees with
who tend to ignore evidence and research that contradicts what they want to
believe, while people who share his own views are more open-minded, skeptical,
and evidence driven. I don’t know when I’ve seen a neater real-world example of
an argument that disproves itself. Good times.
Klein’s actual essay (which Jonah ably took up yesterday,
as did the always wise David Harsanyi at the Federalist), is more serious and
interesting, though.
To some extent Klein’s piece, too, is an example of
confirmation bias in action — as is a great deal of the work of all of us who
write about politics for a living, I’m sure. He opens with what he presents as
a critique of the assumptions underlying our politics, but is probably better
understood as a critique of the assumptions underlying vox.com:
There’s a simple theory underlying much of American politics. It sits hopefully at the base of almost every speech, every op-ed, every article, and every panel discussion. It courses through the Constitution and is a constant in President Obama’s most stirring addresses. It’s what we might call the More Information Hypothesis: the belief that many of our most bitter political battles are mere misunderstandings. The cause of these misunderstandings? Too little information — be it about climate change, or taxes, or Iraq, or the budget deficit. If only the citizenry were more informed, the thinking goes, then there wouldn’t be all this fighting.
I wonder if most people involved in politics in America
really have so little respect for people who disagree with them as to imagine
that the disagreement is just a misunderstanding. Many people seem, rather, to
assume that differences are grounded in different priorities and worldviews
that are rooted in moral and philosophical differences. That assumption is
surely the source of much of the passion and intensity of our politics, and
sometimes also of its depth and seriousness.
Above all, though, I can’t imagine why Klein would think
that this idea “courses through the Constitution” in particular. It seems to me
the Constitution is built on a far more sophisticated grasp of human
limitations and on a sense of the permanence of parties, each of which can only
ever hope to be partially right.
Some members of the founding generation believed
political differences were rooted in inborn dispositions and temperaments and
so were in a sense natural to human societies. Thomas Jefferson often expressed
a form of this view (in terms most agreeable to his own disposition, of
course), writing for instance in an 1802 letter to Joel Barlow:
The division into Whig and Tory is founded in the nature of man; the weakly and nerveless, the rich and the corrupt, seeing more safety and accessibility in a strong executive; the healthy, firm, and virtuous, feeling confidence in their physical and moral resources, and willing to part with only so much power as is necessary for their good government; and, therefore, to retain the rest in the hands of the many, the division will substantially be into Whig and Tory.
Others suggested such differences had more to do with
interests, including material interests. James Madison, for instance, offered a
highly materialist version of this idea in Federalist 10, writing: “From the
protection of different and unequal faculties of acquiring property, the
possession of different degrees and kinds of property immediately results; and
from the influence of these on the sentiments and views of the respective
proprietors, ensues a division of the society into different interests and
parties.” There are other causes of factional differences, Madison
acknowledged, “but the most common and durable source of factions has been the
various and unequal distribution of property.”
Whatever we may think of the materialism of Madison’s
view of this question (and I think it is excessive), the constitutional system
he helped design is surely built on the notion that society would always be
riven by some set of profound differences that would not be readily resolved by
better information. Instead of assuming a position above society from which
different claims can always be objectively adjudicated, the system seeks to
counterbalance those differences and to channel them through complicated
institutions, to prevent any faction from gaining too much power for too long,
and to force any party that seeks to deploy significant public power to
construct a coalition broad enough as to most likely restrain its worst
excesses.
I personally think the sources of our party differences
lie at least as much in different philosophical outlooks as in different
material interests or natural dispositions (though those do matter, surely). I
think our Left and Right, very broadly understood, are each implicitly attached
to a different set of ideas about human perfectibility and human limits,
different notions of what the shape and purpose of society are, and different
understandings of what kinds of knowledge could be available to us to address
social problems. I wrote a book on that subject recently, and won’t belabor it
here. But I think these different outlooks incline us to emphasize different
kinds of questions and prioritize different kinds of goods in the effort to
improve our society, and that this means the Left and Right often talk past one
another in our political debates. It also means that both are very deeply
vulnerable to confirmation bias.
My view of that subject leads me to think that arguments
(and facts and figures and other information) do matter a great deal in
politics, though maybe not as much as any of us might like. But it also leads
me to think that the permanence of the limits of human reason and the fact that
every party only sees part of the whole means no one — not even people who
agree with me — is ever likely to be entirely right when it comes to big,
complicated social questions. In terms of the structure of our governing
institutions, it therefore leads me to the same conclusion Madison reached,
which is that we need a system that keeps all sides from getting too much power
and forces them to confront and compromise with one another in practical terms.
However much we might regret it, this is a system that assumes we will never
fully persuade one another in politics, and indeed that assumes we are probably
all wrong — which we probably are. It is therefore a political system that
makes us less stupid, not (as Klein suggests in the title of his piece) more
so.
But the fact that among the roots of our political
differences is a difference about epistemology — about what we can know in
politics and how we can know it—means that this Madisonian conclusion is often
itself one of the points of debate between Left and Right.
American progressives have long contended that as social
science enables us to overcome some of the limits of what we know, it should
also be permitted to overcome the constitutional limits on what government may
do. They take themselves to be an exception to the rule that all parties see
only parts of the whole, and therefore an exception also to the ubiquity of
confirmation bias, and so they demand an exception to the rule that no party
should have too much raw power. This is basically what Paul Krugman was getting
at.
But the progressives’ understanding of how social science
can come to know society and of how such knowledge might be put into effect has
itself been a point of great contention with conservatives — who tend to think
that a society’s knowledge exists mostly in dispersed forms and therefore that
public policy should work largely by enabling the dispersed social institutions
of civil society, local community, and the market economy to address problems
from the bottom up through incremental trial-and-error learning processes. This
is a view of public policy that is generally compatible with the limits the
constitutional system places on government, while the progressive preference
for consolidated knowledge and centralized action tend to be far less so, and
not by coincidence.
Many serious people on the left don’t believe this
disagreement about the proper way to obtain and act on social knowledge is a
legitimate difference, or rather they treat the technocratic attitude of the
modern Left as common sense and therefore as not requiring justification. The
Left is concerned with ends, they say — the betterment of the poor, the
improvement of living conditions — and is purely pragmatic about means. I’m
sure they believe this quite genuinely, but the means of politics and policy
can only be separated from the ends (which is to say, the means can only be
left unlimited) this way if you take for granted the worldview of the modern
Left and its understanding of how people thrive and how societies work. It is
also no coincidence, therefore, that people who claim that progressivism is
pragmatism strongly incline to centralized technocratic approaches to policy —
which leave little room for experimentation, make it difficult to evaluate
success and failure, and create programs that are very hard to change or
discard when they fail, and therefore aren’t very pragmatic at all.
That progressive preference for centralized expertise and
authority ultimately assumes the possibility of a vantage point outside society
from which the social scientist and social manager can view the whole and not
just parts. Klein quotes Dan Kahan, the Yale professor whose research about
confirmation bias he highlights, articulating the ideal of such detachment: “My
hypothesis is we can use reason to identify the sources of the threats to our
reason and then we can use our reason to devise methods to manage and control
those processes.” This has long been the hope of progressives seeking to use
social science to overcome the limits of politics, and indeed the hope of
rationalist philosophers throughout the history of the West.
But understanding human limitations does not mean we can
overcome them. It only means we can’t pretend they don’t exist. It should point
us toward humility, not hubris. And in politics and policy, understanding the
limitation that Klein highlights should point us away from technocratic
overconfidence and toward an idea of a government that enables society to
address its problems through incremental, local, trial-and-error learning
processes rather than centrally managed wholesale transformations of large
systems.
Klein, to his credit, seems genuinely skeptical about
whether Kahan’s ambitions are plausible. For one thing, unlike Krugman, he
acknowledges the vulnerability of everyone in our politics to confirmation
bias. He accepts the proposition that it’s as prevalent on the Left as on the
Right, though he does seem to have some trouble finding examples on his own
side of the aisle. They are not so hard to come by. He points out, for
instance, that confirmation bias can be especially problematic regarding issues
“where action is needed quickly to prevent a disaster that will happen slowly.”
Madison pointed to the very same problem. And while Klein can only think of conservative
attitudes toward climate change when looking for an example of this, he could
easily have found another instance much closer to home if he were not inclined
to ignore it.
But in the end, it is not clear if Klein accepts
Madison’s notion that these limits on human knowledge and on its effectiveness
are permanent and universal, and so accepts the need for a system that limits
the damage that hubris might cause while making room for a constructive
politics and an effective government. Rather, he suggests that these limits on
our knowledge are a function of systems set up to keep our minds closed.
“Washington is a bitter war between two well-funded, sharply-defined tribes
that have their own machines for generating evidence and their own enforcers of
orthodoxy,” Klein writes. “It’s a perfect storm for making smart people very
stupid.”
“The silver lining,” Klein continues, “is that politics
doesn’t just take place in Washington.” And he suggests that outside the gilded
capital, people should be far better able to judge policies by their outcomes
and remain free of partisan sentiments and of confirmation bias. Here again is
the progressive assumption that, free of the nefarious influence of landed
interests, the people can in fact overcome what only seem to be the limits of
our reason and knowledge. And so, having come around at last to the peculiar
mix of populism and technocracy that has always characterized American
progressivism, Klein ends up suggesting that it is after all our system of
government that is the problem here. He began his essay by wrongly attributing
to the Constitution the view that political differences are just
misunderstandings so that he could conclude by stepping up to defend a version
of that view himself, and could offer his political vision as a vindication of
the constitutional order rather than a rejection of it.
But a rejection of it is what it seems to be. “If
American politics is going to improve, it will be better structures, not better
arguments, that win the day,” Klein concludes.
My own sense is that if American politics is going to
help American society improve, it will be better policies that make that
possible, and the constitutional structures we have — precisely because they
are built upon a realistic understanding of human limits and a sense that
government’s purpose is to sustain the space in which society can function and
to enable everyone to benefit from what happens there — are very well suited to
allowing for that kind of politics of bottom-up improvement. The liberal
welfare state is not. It is the task of conservatives in the coming years to
make to the public—concretely, issue by issue, with evidence and argument, as
both a political vision and a policy agenda — the case for the former over the
latter, secure in the conviction that arguments matter . . . at least up to a
point.
No comments:
Post a Comment