By Jason Lee Steorts
Wednesday, December 28, 2022
Someone in my life wired through intermediaries some aid
money to Ukrainians in the early days of the war. He received back a story of a
Ukrainian woman who fed Russian soldiers several times after they came to her
door. Then one day, while retrieving food from the kitchen, she heard a thud
and, returning to another room, found her husband with his throat slit. And
then she was taken upstairs and raped repeatedly.
I cannot confirm the report, but it is plausible. Many such horrors have been confirmed and reported.
I have wanted to share this particular horror story and
to write something about the war. The enormity of the topic has left me
wordless. But President Zelensky, of Ukraine, asked that the world think at
Christmas about the sufferings of his people at Christmas, so herewith a
handful of thoughts.
1.
We should not assume that atrocities such as those
committed against the woman and her husband are necessarily absent from just
wars. But we should not draw a false moral equivalence, either. The purpose and
conduct of a war matter. A just war in which an atrocity is committed will be
just in part if the perpetrators of the injustice are punished justly.
2.
An unjust war of territorial acquisition and a just war
of territorial defense would, even if producing equal atrocities, be morally
unequal as to the purpose of the war.
And “equal atrocities” does not describe the
Russo–Ukrainian war.
3.
It is worthwhile to think about the war if you are
thinking about the debate in world politics right now between defenders and
critics of nationalism.
4.
Some Western defenders of nationalism who oppose the war
and want Ukraine to win say that Russia’s acts in Ukraine are imperialist, not
nationalist, and that the Ukrainian defense is nationalist. They have a point.
President Putin, of Russia, has denied in writing that Ukrainians are an independent
people with a distinct national identity. (English translation via the
Kremlin here; website not secure.) In the same essay, he says that
a group of individuals may choose to form a new nation provided that this
happens according to a fair process; that the future of Ukraine is up to the
Ukrainian people; and that negotiations between Russia and Ukraine should take
Ukraine’s pre-Soviet borders as their starting point. (From the Ukrainian point
of view this would of course be to start with an unacceptable territorial
cession.) The overall view is somewhat unclear, and his words, as he concedes,
“can be interpreted in many possible ways.” How to take them is for each to
judge. That the invasion last year appeared calculated to decapitate the
Ukrainian government and seize Kyiv might be thought to indicate his genuine
ambitions at the time.
In any case, if the world acquiesced to a denial of
Ukrainian distinctness, it would have accepted the erasure of the national
identity of the Ukrainian people, who have proven at terrible cost their
communal coherence. Such an erasure would not only contradict the principle of
nationalism; it would be a moral atrocity and a denial of reality to boot.
5.
Some Western critics of nationalism, on the other hand,
say that Russia’s invasion was not imperialist but nationalist: that the war is
fought in the name of Russian nationhood, with the aims of retaking territory
that had formerly been under Moscow’s control and of securing the interests of
ethnic Russians who do not wish to be part of the Ukrainian national state.
This may look like imperialism in Kyiv and Lviv, but in Moscow it is a matter
of national identity, and in the Donbas it depends on whom you ask.
6.
How then to decide a dispute of this sort justly?
As always when interests conflict or are thought to, we
need a standard that can be adopted by all disputants and therefore regarded by
all as fair.
7.
It is not a matter of whether, in practice, all would agree
to any such standard, since that would be nearly impossible.
The question is rather what standard all should agree
to.
8.
Could one turn the principle of nationalism itself into
such a standard? If everyone were nationalist, would not everyone respect all
nations?
9.
If so, nationalism would reduce to a sort of generic
communitarianism.
That is, each nation would perceive the interests of
other nations as well as its own, all would honor the interests of all, and
what I have called a “mutually respectful relativistic nationalism”
would prevail.
10.
But what if some nations did not want to respect the
interests of other nations, wishing instead to advance their own at the cost of
others’? How would we try to persuade such a nation to abandon what might be
called “egotistical nationalism”?
We would have to talk about something other than
national interest at this point, since conflicting national interests are
precisely what the practitioners of egotistical nationalism deny should be
weighed equally. We would have to talk about the interests of human beings as
such.
11.
Could someone not reply to me, “Very well: All people
value their nations, just as they value their individual interests. National
interests may conflict, but this is just the problem of egotism, as your own
terminology suggests. ‘Egotistical nationalism’ is no greater a challenge to
nationalism as an ideal than is personal egotism to the ideals of individual
ethics.”
12.
No. The answer is no. For the situations are not similar
after all.
The problem of individual egotism is the problem faced by
the woman, any number of them, who asks not to have her husband murdered and
herself raped and who receives the reply that the attacker understands her but
does not care.
The problem of conflicting national interests is that her
needs as an individual, whatever they be, cannot even be weighed. This is
because nationalism lays its normative foundation above the individual, at the
level of the national community as such. Her life and her family simply do not
figure into an accounting of what is good for Russia qua Russia.
13.
This is not to say that a nationalist nation will choose
to be cruel. But if it makes the national interest its sole decisive principle,
it deprives the woman whose husband is about to bleed to death of any
necessarily shared criterion of judgment, any language she can speak to it that
it is guaranteed to understand. If it feels any regard for her as a person,
this is only because it has taken in ethical considerations extraneous to
nationalism per se.
And it is not as if the Russian state has shown remorse
or embarrassment over the butchers of Bucha and the perpetrators of similar atrocities
elsewhere in Ukraine.
14.
This is why it is necessary to make individual interests
the final standard of judgment of right and wrong in politics and geopolitics.
We do not want to fail to count anyone.
By starting with individual interests, we will pick up
the interests of nations and other communities, which must be interests of some
individual or group of individuals, living or to come, if they are interests at
all. Communities are not sentient as communities; their value
is felt only by the individuals who compose them.
The woman not only makes her plea in a tongue foreign to
her attackers. She addresses it to an abstraction.
15.
The need to count everyone’s interests, as I have
written elsewhere, requires that the consent of the governed be the
standard of political legitimacy. Since I see the Ukrainian cause as an attempt
of the majority population to govern itself by mutual consent, I favor the
cause of the Ukrainian nation.
16.
Along a disputed border where ethnicities are mixed, the
question of consent will not be so simple. But acts of coercion are still
morally prohibited, and we should see clearly that defense against coercion is
not itself coercion.
I take Russia to be the state actor that coerced, by
invading first Crimea and then other parts of Ukraine.
I also take Russia to have been the main force behind the
bloody unrest in eastern Ukraine these past years, although I do not deny that
acts of unjust violence, including murder, have been committed against
pro-Russian Ukrainians (as in the Maidan protests in Odesa that Putin mentions
in his essay).
17.
Please pay attention to and remember always what a border
adjustment amid a mixed population can look like.
Yoram Hazony, whose writings I value despite my
disagreements with them, writes in The Virtue of Nationalism that
“the aspirations of national states tend to produce petty wars whose purpose is
adjustments in the hierarchy of power among them, or to achieve an alteration
in the boundaries among them.” This could be true, but “adjustments” could just
as well look like the Russo–Ukrainian war or the horrors attendant to the
breakup of Yugoslavia. Hazony’s reference to war “between the Serbs and the
Croats,” for instance, is curious in its omission of the term “ethnic
cleansing” and any equivalent language — in its theoretic blindness, that is,
to the attempted erasure of one national identity where two conflicted. He
wants minority populations to be treated decently, but this wish must spring from
normative sources other than the one he makes foundational to his theory, and
must draw him finally into the sort of universalist political ethics that he
abjures.
18.
Nor should we overlook the tragedy of the war for the
Russian people and for the soldiers being offered up as a kind of sacrifice to
the abstraction of national ego. The New York Times’ transcripts of
intercepted phone calls from Russian soldiers are heartbreaking.
19.
It is possible to misperceive a situation drastically.
Maybe the Russian government did think the war would be
quick and the result welcomed by or beneficial to most Ukrainians. This would
in fact be consistent with the belief that Ukraine is not a distinct nation but
rather part of Russia. An invasion thus becomes a reunion.
Western nations including the United States have also
made errors of judgment, for example in thinking that the invasion of Iraq
would be mild in its damage and quickly produce a stabler and juster Iraq
governed by Iraqis.
But far from undermining the distinction we have drawn,
this comparison crystallizes it. “Stable” and “just” and “governed by [the
people]” are part of an ethical language we all can speak just because we are
human beings. “Country A must be forced to return to Country B because Country
A really is Country B” is not; it is irreducibly particularist.
20.
It is awkward that the people making claims such as mine
live in countries whose own histories have included outrages of inconsistency
with the claims.
One really cannot look at what the United States did to
American Indians as anything other than a genocide. (For details on the
foremost atrocity, consult Unworthy Republic, by Claudio Saunt.) It
is not better than the Chinese treatment of the Uyghurs, for example; to me it
seems worse.
One really cannot deny that the United States fought wars
of territorial acquisition that were unjust.
One really cannot deny that the United States has
massacred civilians.
21.
In one way this is not a problem of hypocrisy, since the
people who did those things are gone and no one is obliged to be as bad as his
forebears.
It is therefore salutary to discard Chesterton’s idea of
tradition as a “democracy of the dead.” If we continue their ways it should be
only because we see the goodness of them. We do not owe it to
the dead to repeat their errors. If they care about us, they should in fact
want us not to do so. They should want us instead to correct their errors, for
our own benefit and that of those to come.
22.
But even if the entire world forswore injustice today,
accidents of history still would have distributed most unevenly the fruits,
comestible or foul, of past injustices.
To that problem I have no answer. But I know that the
answer is not to go on practicing injustice forever, and that the sin is the
greater the clearer the alternative seen.
No comments:
Post a Comment