By Kevin D. Williamson
Monday, October 10, 2022
Welcome
to the third installment of Economics for English Majors, which is appearing as
a series of standalone essays until my new Dispatch newsletter, Wanderland,
officially launches next Monday. (Please do join if you haven’t.) I’m taking
advantage of the temporary format to write some longer pieces—the ones in the
newsletter will be shorter, usually. But, since there’s no newsletter real
estate to take up, for now I’ll go long.
Another
way of thinking about that is that, at the moment, the opportunity cost of
writing longer E4EM essays is relatively low. Opportunity cost is one of the
three or four most important concepts in economics, especially for
non-economists who want to understand economic thinking in the public policy
context. It is simple enough, but still underappreciated, in part because we
tend to look at opportunity cost from the consumer point of view and forget all
about the production side.
The
fundamental issue in economics is scarcity. Scarcity is a fact of
life: No matter how rich we become as a society, and no matter how much
material abundance we enjoy, there is never enough to go around to satisfy
every desire of every person: Some goods are naturally limited (there are only
so many Rembrandt paintings), some goods are rivalrous in
consumption (if Steve smokes a cigar, Jonah can’t smoke the same cigar), and
our desire to consume goods that require work to produce (see last week’s discussion of Say’s Law) conflicts with
our practically infinite appetite for leisure time. As much as it may grieve
David French, you can’t plant turnips and play World of Warcraft at
the same time. You have to choose one.
That
special application of scarcity—“If you want x, you
have to forgo y”—is opportunity cost.
You all
know that, of course. I’m just laying some groundwork.
Opportunity
cost is not exclusively an economic issue as such. As Ludwig von Mises points
out in his famous essay “Economic Calculation in the
Socialist Commonwealth”—which we’ll be revisiting directly—there are all sorts of tradeoffs in
life that we cannot put a monetary price on: Sometimes, we have to choose
between having a hydroelectric plant or the beauty of an unspoiled waterfall,
Mises writes, or choose between income and honor. (Mises and F.A. Hayek—émigrés who
provided the Austrian school of economics its name—were obliged to abandon
their native Austria after its annexation by Nazi Germany and thus had the
example of richly rewarded collaborators to illuminate that latter issue.) To
value the beauty of the waterfall or one’s honor is not irrational, Mises
argued, but such dilemmas fall outside of the scope of economic
calculation per se. In the context of an exchange-based economy—as
opposed to that socialist commonwealth—money provides a standard and a unit to
help us to impose some rigor on our treatment of opportunity cost.
Say you
want to buy a house in San Antonio, where the median home price is about
$320,000. (The median house price in San Antonio is six times the median
household income, and that is pretty high; but the median house price in San
Francisco is about 13 times the median household income. There’s American
politics circa 2022 in a nutshell.) Say you can afford a nicer-than-average
house, but a nice house is not the only thing you want in life. If the price
difference between the house you really want and the house you
can live with is $20,000 (which you are going to spread over a
30-year mortgage) then probably you make the stretch, because $20,000 won’t
even get you a new Honda Civic. But if the difference is $300,000, that’s a
Bentley Flying Spur with some options. It’s about 75,000 venti lattes at
Starbucks, or 30 Gibson ES-350s like Chuck Berry used
to play, or four
pizzas, because $70,000 pizza with gold in the crust apparently is a thing that
exists in our age of angst and deprivation. Actually, $300,000 is about 4.29 of
those pizzas, but I don’t think you can order 29 percent of a $70,000 gold
pizza—even in Times Square, they won’t sell that by the slice. That’s four
years at Princeton at the rack rate with some money left over. Maybe you don’t
want any of those things (I’d take the Gibson) but have lots of other things in
your wish list—without money to act as a yardstick to simplify what Mises calls
our “oppressive plenitude,” figuring out what you’re potentially giving up by
choosing the more expensive house gets pretty difficult. But money works only
when there’s free exchange—because what we are interested in is how much people
actually value Princeton educations and golden pizzas, not how much some guy at
a desk backed by guys with bayonets says you should value this
or that.
What
Mises gets into—and you should really read the whole essay; it’s both
interesting and accessible—is the even more complex issue of “higher order”
goods. In one of those desert-island economies that economists like to write
about, with two guys trading fish and coconuts (Mises even considers the case
of Robinson Crusoe, an even simpler desert-island economy), we can probably
just about handle the question of how much of each commodity to produce, the
answer being: more. There isn’t much opportunity cost for the
fisherman on the desert island to spend an extra hour or two fishing—what else
is he going to do all day? But if you decide to build a steel plant that sits
on 40 acres of land, takes up billions of dollars in capital, and employs 1,000
workers, then your opportunity cost is considerable and difficult to apprehend
in terms of barter exchange: The opportunity cost is every conceivable thing
that land and that capital and that labor might have been used for
instead.
Mises’
argument in its simplest form (and I will go ahead and say this is
oversimplified even if sufficient for our purposes here) is that the problem
facing central planning—which is the fundamental task of the socialist economic
power—is not that central planning is inefficient or wasteful or
prone to error and corruption or anything
like that but is, in fact, impossible.
How
so?
If the
state owns the means of production, then there can be no prices attached
to the factors of production, these being res extra commercium.
Without the means of rigorous apples-to-apples comparison afforded by prices,
there can be no real economic calculation, and hence no rational central planning
worth the name. We cannot make rational decisions about opportunity costs if we
cannot define what it is we are giving up: You cannot make rational tradeoffs
if you do not have a reasonably precise idea of what it is you are trading away
and what it is you are getting. Even if the Soviet Union had been run by people
who were both enormously intelligent and morally upright to the point of
saintliness (and it surely was not, though it had some of those very
intelligent men, at least) it still would have failed, because its major
problem was not corruption, which is universal—it was that the central planners
had set themselves an impossible task.
Markets
embed economic information in society where it is accessible to those who make
decisions about what to produce and to consume and where to invest and to
spend. Central planners do not have access to that knowledge, and even the most
intelligent of them would not have the capacity to act rationally on that
knowledge if they could somehow acquire and compile it, because the sheer
amount of knowledge—often short-lived and contingent knowledge—held in the
brains and experience of the tens of thousands of people who make up the steel
industry is too much for the 12 brains on the steel committee at the Department
of Economic Planning. This is what the followers of Mises and Hayek have called
the “knowledge problem.”
That the
Soviet Union was an economic (and moral) disaster is well-understood. But we
have other examples that we can draw from. The collapse of the Roman Empire
brought with it a collapse in trade and the use of money in much of Europe, a
condition that lasted until the revival of the money-enabled economy that led
to the Renaissance. A famous Anglo-Saxon document known as the Burghal
Hidage (You really going to cite the Burghal Hidage at
this hour on a Monday morning, Williamson? Damned skippy I am!) catalogs the
fortresses (“burhrs”) of the medieval English kingdoms and the taxes
that were due to each of them based on “hides,” a hide being
(originally and approximately) a quantity of land sufficient for the support of
a household of 10. Taxes due were based on the number of hides assigned
to a particular jurisdiction. But, of course, there was little money in
circulation, so the taxes ended up being positively comical to the modern
reader, with one often-cited law demanding a tax consisting of “10 vats of
honey, 300 loaves, 12 ambers of Welsh ale, 30 ambers of clear ale, 2 full-grown
cows or 10 wethers, 10 geese, 20 hens, 10 cheeses, a full amber of butter, 5
salmon, 20 pounds of fodder, and 100 eels” for every 10 hides on
the tax roll. Why 100 eels and not 101? Do you think this was the result of
a calculation?
The
economy described in the Burghal Hidage offered practically
everything a central planner could ask for: a severely limited range of
commodities, few luxury goods to fight over, mostly unfree labor, and a
political agency with the power to exercise something very close to total
surveillance and total control over economic production and consumption, which
was mostly local in character and for that reason much easier to manage than
our high-tech modern global economy. Bernie Sanders wouldn’t have to worry
about these peasants having 57 different kinds of deodorant. (I have been to a
Bernie Sanders rally, and the great problem I detected there was not an
oppressive superabundance of hygiene products.) The medieval manorial economy
wasn’t quite the economists’ desert island, but it was pretty close. There were
no pesky private-equity firms in the mix, to be sure. The result of those
economic arrangements was a very long period of economic and cultural
stagnation (at best) or decline (often enough) that persisted until the
reemergence of the social features that still characterize prosperous and dynamic
societies today: urban life, trade, access to financial services and distant
markets, reasonably stable money (remember stable money?), mobility of labor
and capital, etc.
If it
seems like we have wandered far from opportunity cost, we haven’t. What the
medieval peasants lacked was what the Soviet subjects lacked: choice. What
every central planner—including every trade protectionist who wants to defend
Americans from the bane of dastardly foreigners scheming to sell us goods we
want at attractive prices—proposes to take away from people is that same thing:
choice. Markets can tap all that miraculous human knowledge and human ingenuity
only where there is choice. Where there is no choice, there is no question of
thinking rationally about opportunity cost, because there is no
opportunity—there is only doing what you are ordered to do.
Mises,
bless him, wrote for grown-ups—i.e., for people who understand that we have to
make choices and that our choices are constrained by reality, by the facts on
the ground, and that choosing x means forgoing a practically
infinite variety of things in the category not-x. The utopians—and the
socialists are not the only kind of utopian, or possibly even the most
dangerous kind at the moment—tell a different story: that we don’t have to make
hard choices, that we can have everything we want at whatever price we like (“Let us kill him, and we'll have corn
at our own price”)
as long as we give up one little thing: the power to choose our own
tradeoffs.
Of
course, as Hayek pointed out, choice doesn’t cease to exist in the
command-and-control economy. It’s just that the power to choose is taken away
from most people and concentrated in the hands of a powerful few. It is one of
the ironies of our time that the people who advertise their commitment to
“American greatness” work from the false and unfounded belief that Americans
are too stupid and too weak to make their own decisions. Funny kind of
greatness, that.
No comments:
Post a Comment