By Michael Brendan Dougherty
Wednesday, July 14, 2021
There’s a certain type of intellect that rebels at
the idea of nations and nationalism. George Orwell comes to mind. For rather
understandable reasons — like being on the side of the communists in the
Spanish Civil War, and then watching Hitler march all over Europe — he hated
nationalism and wrote very witheringly of what it did to the minds of
nationalists. He viewed figures such as G. K. Chesterton as those who
“transferred” their nationalism onto a nation not their own, which caused
Chesterton to say things about France that he could never quite bring himself
to say about his own England, whose faults he knew.
But Orwell’s essay “Notes on Nationalism” is surprisingly
unsatisfactory.
Nationalism, on the other hand, is
inseparable from the desire for power. The abiding purpose of every nationalist
is to secure more power and more prestige, not for himself but for the nation
or other unit in which he has chosen to sink his own individuality.
He contrasts it with patriotism, which he maintains is
always defensive and defensible. All sins related to one’s country are
nationalist sins, and all noble deeds become patriotic. His definition of
nationalism turns out to be nothing more or less than a collection of all the
sins of self-interest, and self-seeking, but transferred from the individual to
a collective. The problems of this definition are revealed in his own essay
once he turns away from World War II–era Japan and tries to look at Welsh or
Irish nationalism.
While he can spy that these nationalisms sometimes take
up a mythology of greatness, he simply can’t bear to understand that a
nationalist movement might seek the goal of political independence even when he
understands that the new state will be much less powerful on the world stage
than the one he is in. And that he might seek to wield power in this new state
in order to stop injustices that are the result of ongoing administration by
the incumbent non-nationals.
Bret Devereaux, a professor of ancient history at North
Carolina State University, is another mind that rebels against nationalism.
Ahead of the Fourth of July he wrote a lovely and long essay, “My Country Isn’t a Nation.” He proposes a definition of nation, as a people, and
then tries to vindicate the claim that the United States is a really an
“un-nation” that cannot be made to fit the idea of a nation, and that rejects
it in key respects. Instead of an American people, we just have American
citizens — he proposes.
But his definition of a nation is too strict, and too
ludicrously literal. In an odd way it is this anti-nationalist who ends up
being a prisoner of German romantics. In trying to disqualify the United States
he ends up disqualifying all nations. He writes:
The idea of the “nation” has
always been fixed around the notion of a common birth or more correctly
the myth of common birth. There are other elements in
defining a nation of course: the group typically needs to be large, inhabit a
shared, recognizable territory, and share common elements of culture
(especially language) and a common history. But it is no accident that the
common birth, the natio of nation, is central. A nation,
precisely because it is supposed to share a common culture and history, is an
entity that is imagined to extend both into the past and into the future,
recreating itself, generation to generation; it is through the common birth
that the common culture and history are supposedly shared. After all, a common
history assumes some commonality stretching back to a prior generation.
[Devereaux’s emphasis]
He also takes in hand the objection that nations and
nation-states are not “natural” or “organic.”
The nation in this sense is not
a social or political form that exists in the wild, but is instead a thing that
humans can invent and is usually the product of state-building
rather than an organic cultural expression (for instance, the
uniformity of French is a product of the government in Paris’ efforts to make
it so, not an organic feature of the “French people”). Nations and
nationalism and especially nation-states are relatively recent
things; we are discussing people who until quite recently did not see
themselves as having a common origin or destiny and who now claim their
ancestors to have been of common stock typically in contradiction to
the views of those very ancestors.
This has become a very common objection, but on inspection
it is almost quite silly, for reasons we’ll come to in a moment. Devereaux
applies the same strict rules about territory and language.
Because the American nation isn’t defined by an exclusive
ethnic core of people whose place of origin was within the current territorial
boundaries of the American state, it is not a nation, for him. In fact, many of
our ancestors were in conflict with each other. Therefore, we can’t have a
shared history or a shared story. He writes that “to be an American means that someone,
somewhere in your heritage (likely many someones) broke the
chain of connection between you and whatever mythical notional nation you may
have otherwise been part of (mind you, not all Americans’ ancestors were given
a choice in that rupture).”
If a nation must be defined this way, Devereaux is right;
there are no “American people” and no American nation.
But then there are no Hungarians, English, or French
people, either.
Devereaux’s strictness is debilitating. Let’s take one
example. Holding to Devereaux’s definitions, there cannot be an Irish people or
an Irish nation. Not all of the ancestors of those living in Ireland share in
the Irish people’s ancient past, and many of them viewed themselves as in
conflict with each other. The Viking invaders who eventually settled and
founded what is now Dublin were not around during the golden age of the Irish
in the early Middle Ages, when Irish-speaking monks were founding monasteries
around Europe. Vikings were destroying those monasteries, in fact. Later came
the Normans, whose role in Irish history was to weaken the power of the
traditional Gaelic elites, ahead of further English incursion. Perhaps the
physical descendants of the Gael can’t even lay claim to their own ancestry,
because the Normans imparted parts of their language to the Irish. Modern
French has “garçon” for boy; Irish has “gasur.” Or
“chambre” for room, which in Irish became “seomra.”
So, is there no Irish nation? Well, of course there is.
The descendants of those in the Viking settlements became intermarried with the
ancient inhabitants and adopted and adapted to their ways, while leaving a
trace of themselves on the island. The Hiberno-Normans were also Gaelicized
over time, and then over time, as new conflicts became pertinent, their
Catholic faith tended to place them beside the traditional Gael against those
arriving from Tudor England.
The existence of Breton language or Cornish does not mean
that there is no such thing as French or English nations — nor would Frenchness
or Englishness cease to exist if new research or archaeology or DNA tests
changed the relative admixture of Gaul and Frank, or Pict and Norman.
Devereaux places emphasis on “myth” and “invention,” but
this is what people do when they come together, and it is not less real because
it took human will or effort. My family has myth and lore attached to it —
stories that have been embellished as they have been retold in the generations.
But that my children are partly physically descended from their mother does not
impeach their connection to the family lore that exists on my side. Pointing
out that our Slovak, Italian, and Irish ancestors didn’t know each other does
not mean that my family does not exist. That is, people who break the chain of
national connection in one generation form new bonds in the next, because they
are people. Those bonds become stronger over time as previous divisions are
melted away — either by shared language and the further development of custom,
by intermarriage, or just by the process of sharing a territory
together. Even the most romantic of romantic nationalists are capable of
admitting the diverse sources of the national stock. Thomas Davis proclaimed of
Ireland, “This country of ours is no sandbank, thrown up by some recent caprice
of earth. It is an ancient land, honoured in the archives of civilisation,
traceable into antiquity by its piety, its valour, and its sufferings. Every
great European race has sent its stream to the river of Irish mind.”
National identities, like other identities, can be
various. They can be overlapping, or subject to total absorption. A Frenchman
who marries into a family in Brittany may not himself have had ancestors who
spoke Breton, but perhaps his grandchildren will speak it. They will have a
Breton identity and a French national one. A Hungarian Jew will not be
“Hungarian” in the exact same way as ethnic Magyars. Most Hungarian Jews will
wish to retain their Jewish identity by virtue of their faith. But, by virtue of
their place in a Hungarian city and as Hungarian speakers, they will in certain
senses participate in Hungarian national identity as well. And we should not be
anxious to define “nation” so strictly that we discourage these overlapping and
admixed arrangements.
And the same is true of Americans. The fact that we have
no dominant common ancestors, and that some of us can trace our ancestry to
people who were in conflict with each other, is not an impediment to becoming a
people and living as one. This doesn’t obliterate our sub-national, ethnic, and
racial identities — or it doesn’t have to obliterate them. There is much I
cannot really know directly of the African-American experience, but the idea
that I share nothing with Jackie Robinson or Dave Chappelle, or with my
Filipino neighbors, beyond “citizenship” is silly. We share this land, we have
a common language, we share and contribute to a common culture, even as we have
our parochial interests and our conflicts. My ancestors were not here during
the Founding. The freedom of my ancestors’ co-religionists in Quebec was listed
among the grievances that impelled the political founding of this nation. But
that grievance has faded away over time. And so the affection of people like
mine, our ability to internalize George Washington as the Founder of “our
nation” and “one of us,” grows. We share in the faults, burdens, triumphs, and
glories of a shared American people.
No comments:
Post a Comment